New on the site: Michi-bot. An intelligent assistant based on the writings of Rabbi Michael Avraham.

Parashat the Children of Gad and Reuben: B. Halakhic Implications (Column 643)

With God’s help

Disclaimer: This post was translated from Hebrew using AI (ChatGPT 5 Thinking), so there may be inaccuracies or nuances lost. If something seems unclear, please refer to the Hebrew original or contact us for clarification.

In the previous column we examined the structure of the story of the tribes of Gad and Reuben and the stipulation Moses made with them. I explained that the Torah found it important to present the process in detailed stages: first the context, then the rationale (what the parties want on the legal level), and finally the mode of implementation—by way of a stipulation. I distinguished there between the different stages, and we saw that the description of the rationale resembles the description of the stipulation, though there are differences between them. In the context there is not really a double condition presented, but rather a commitment to participate in the fighting. By contrast, a condition does not impose an obligation on the one being conditioned, but only limits the legal effect (i.e., the granting of the inheritance is conditioned on participation in battle). In our case Moses adds the stipulation in order to prod the tribes of Gad and Reuben to stand by their commitment. This is done within the framework of the contract they conclude, in which it is agreed to transfer the inheritance east of the Jordan (the act) only if the tribes of Gad and Reuben take part in the fighting (the condition).

What, in fact, is the Torah trying to teach through this detailed structure? Why was it so important to distinguish between these stages and to repeat again and again the point that the granting of the inheritance is in exchange for participation in battle? One might say that all of this appears here incidentally, merely because in practice there was a stipulation and the Torah is only describing it. But the repetitions and the detail hint that there is something more here. The Talmud and the Rishonim understood that all this appears here intentionally to teach the idea of a stipulation and the manner in which it must be implemented (the laws of conditions—mishpetei ha-tena’im). The assumption is that without the Torah’s innovation we would not know that a stipulation is an available mechanism in halakhah, even though in ordinary legal systems it is taken for granted that one can attach conditions. To understand this better, I must first preface an important distinction between halakhic law and ordinary legal systems.

Halakhah and Law

At the beginning of any legal contract there appears a rationale that contains the goals and interests of both parties. The contract itself expresses the legal path to realize those goals. If one manages to find a suitable legal path to implement the parties’ rationale—a contract is made, in which the “how” is detailed. Is it possible that no legal path will be found to do so? In other words, could it be that although the parties desire something, there is no valid contract that realizes it? If that is the situation, then beyond clarifying the parties’ interests and desires, in order to draft a valid contract one must check that a valid legal path exists to do it. This is the meaning of the Torah’s innovation in the story of the tribes of Gad and Reuben: there is a legal path to carry out such desires. That path is the stipulation. I will now explain why the possibility of stipulating is not as trivial as one might think.

In ordinary civil law, freedom of contract is the norm. Two parties who seek certain interests from each other can conclude whatever contract they wish in order to realize them. If it is clear from the contract what each party undertakes, then the contract is valid. This means that the law as such does not impose restrictions on the kinds of contracts; therefore, in principle, anything one wants can be realized. The only problem within this framework of thought is to express it clearly in the contract and clarify precisely what the parties desire—and that is the lawyer’s job. Sometimes, indeed, there are cogent (mandatory) statutory requirements, i.e., provisions that cannot be contracted around because they are dictated by the legislature and not left to the parties’ will. For example, an employee’s waiver of his basic rights is not possible. Those rights are mandatory provisions of the law (even if the employee signs that he waived such rights, it does not stand, and the employer must grant them). But these are not limitations that derive from the absence of a legal mechanism; rather, they reflect the legislator’s desire to protect the weaker side. The legislator implicitly assumes that the party who “waived” his rights didn’t truly want to, and therefore does not allow it. Thus, such provisions are still an expression of the parties’ will, not a limitation due to the lack of a legal way to effect the parties’ will. I will not address such limitations here. My question is whether there can be legal limitations on freedom of contract as such: can a legal system say that although both parties clearly desire something, there is no legal possibility to realize it?

I think that in law, in principle, this does not exist. By contrast, in halakhah the situation is different. There are limitations on contracts that stem from the legal mechanisms themselves. That is, there are things that cannot be done within halakhah despite the parties’ desire and agreement, simply because there is no valid legal mechanism that accomplishes it. For example, in halakhah one cannot transfer title in an object that has not yet come into existence (davar she-lo ba la-olam). Simply put, this is not due to the parties’ intentions (though some explained it as a lack of “gemirat da’at”—finalized intent—but in my view this explanation is highly dubious), but because halakhah does not allow acquiring such a thing even if they want it. The same applies to transferring rights in an intangible (davar she-ein bo mamash)—again, some explained the problem as one of “gemirat da’at,” but I do not find that convincing either. I will go even further. Halakhah recognizes new forms of acquisition that are practiced in society or a given guild, and accepts their validity (kinyan sitomta—the merchants’ custom). Some Rishonim wrote that even if there is a prevalent custom to transfer title in a non-existent object or in an intangible, it is not halakhically valid. The reason is that where the issue is “gemirat da’at,” a clear custom attests to a finalized intent by the parties, and thus such consent is valid. But in matters not related to finalized intent, rather to a halakhic limitation—something not performable at the legal level—then a custom cannot help. A custom cannot make the impossible possible. What lies behind the halakhic limitations on acquiring non-existent or intangible things is not the parties’ intentions but a halakhic constraint, and halakhah does not view a custom that recognizes such acquisitions as something valid.

In several places in the past (see, for example, in my article “What Is a Chalut?”, in my article on acquisition in halakhah, in my article “Deception and Intellectual Property,” and more) I pointed out that the root of the matter lies in the ontic-metaphysical conception underlying halakhah. Law tends to view legal acts as conventions—agreements between individuals or society at large—and once they are agreed upon through the accepted path (legislation) they receive legal force. But precisely for that reason their force does not attest to any truth, only to the agreement of society; nothing more. By contrast, the halakhic conception (at least as I understand it) assumes that legal acts reflect a metaphysical reality. Thus, for example, when one creates a halakhic effect such as ownership, that is actually an expression of some change in reality itself and not merely a legal convention acknowledging a result. When Reuven sells a field to Shimon, it is not only a social convention that the field is now Shimon’s and not Reuven’s. Something happened in reality itself. The act of acquisition creates an abstract entity—chalut (legal effect)—that now “rests” upon the asset, or upon the woman, or upon the heave-offering, etc., and thereby they become connected to another person or receive a different halakhic status. These are examples that halakhic norms reflect a meta-legal reality (ideas, if you will). From this I explained in the articles cited that there is a difference between saying “the woman is betrothed (mekudeshet)” and saying “I imposed upon her the halakhic effect of betrothal.” The former is not identical to the latter but rather its consequence. The same difference obtains between saying “I bought a field” and saying “I imposed upon it the legal effect of ownership.” The first is a consequence of the second. In my articles I elaborated on this and showed several implications.

In any case, if this is the situation, we can better understand the two examples given above. One cannot impose ownership upon an intangible even if both parties absolutely desire it, because there is nothing for the legal effect to “rest” upon. The thing does not exist in the world, so nothing can be attached to it (no legal effect can be imposed). The same holds for something not yet in existence. The limitations are metaphysical—as if there are spiritual laws of nature that do not allow the creation of such a legal effect even if both parties want it. Just like someone who wants to be present in a fire and not be burned, or to fly through the air—he cannot. The laws of nature do not allow it. Since halakhah views legal norms as expressions of a factual meta-halakhic reality, it is no wonder that halakhah contains limitations on legal states. Not every meta-legal reality can necessarily be created. In halakhah it is not like ordinary legal systems that see laws as conventions (and therefore anything we decide will be valid—there are no built-in legal limitations there).

Application to Stipulations

From such a perspective, one might have thought that even if the parties truly wish to create a contract that includes a condition (i.e., this is the rationale that would appear at the contract’s outset and clarifies that this is indeed the parties’ will), still it cannot be implemented because halakhah does not allow it. There is no such contract in halakhah; therefore their intentions will not be realized. We saw that in an ordinary legal system, once you present the rationale there is no barrier to creating a contract. But in halakhah you might present a rationale and discover there is no legal way to implement it.

I think this is the innovation learned from the “Parashat Tena’im”: after presenting the parties’ rationale, the Torah rules that there is indeed such a contract. There is a way to realize these desires. That is why the Torah insists on detailing all the stages we saw: after presenting the rationale, Moses innovates that this rationale can be implemented in halakhah—by the mechanism of a condition. The stipulation appears here not merely as a description of what happened, but to teach us that there is a mechanism of condition in halakhah. Therefore the Talmud and Rishonim see this passage as the source for the laws of stipulations, and they, of course, assume that such a source is needed. That is, without the source we wouldn’t know that one may make stipulations or how to do so.

What Was the Problem?

On the face of it, this is puzzling. In every legal system in the world it is accepted that one may make conditions; they did not require the Torah’s innovations for this. So why does halakhah require such an innovation? Why should we not derive it logically: if a person expressed that he did not want the contract unless some condition is met, then given that the condition was not met, there is no party will here and the contract is not valid. Think of a case where a man divorced his wife on condition that she not drink wine. If she did drink wine, in such a case he did not wish to divorce her, so how could one think that she is nevertheless divorced? Why do we need the Torah’s innovation that one may stipulate? This need can be explained in several ways; I will bring two.

A. Retroactive Causal Effect

If a condition operated by the mechanism of “igla’i milta le-mafrea” (a later clarification of what had always been the case), then indeed it would seem that the mechanism of the condition is simple and requires no innovation: it simply becomes clear retroactively that this was the parties’ will. There is no causal influence backwards in time. But we saw that—at least according to R. Shimon Shkop—the condition operates by the mechanism of “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea,” namely there is causal influence backwards along the timeline (where the cause is later than the effect). The wife’s drinking wine uproots the divorce that took place in the past. We also saw that halakhah views itself in an ontic-metaphysical manner.

If the condition were merely a convention, as ordinary legal systems assume, then if the parties want such a contract there is no reason they could not do it. But if halakhah is based on creating meta-legal facts in reality (the spiritual realm), then there is something factual here that is brought about by a future cause. There would indeed be room to say that such a mechanism cannot be created, and therefore a condition is impossible. It is possible that this is the Torah’s innovation in the story of Gad and Reuben: there is such a meta-legal mechanism. In effect we learn from here that in the meta-legal realm there can be causal influence that runs backwards in time. Moreover, the Torah’s very need to innovate the possibility of a condition hints that R. Shimon Shkop was right and a condition is not merely a retroactive clarification of existing information, but a reversal of a fact from future to past; thus there really is a problem of reverse causality in conditions. The Torah innovated that it is nevertheless possible.

B. “Kaltah Kinyano” (“The Acquisition-Act Has Concluded”)

Another way to understand the difficulty in the mechanism of conditions is based on the principle called “kaltah kinyano.” The source is the Ran on Nedarim 28b. He explains there that after an act has concluded, one cannot return to it and affect its results:

דמהא שמעינן לדיני ממונות שהאומר לחבירו לך חזק וקני שדה או שתהא נתונה לך מעכשיו עד שאלך לירושלים וחזר וקנאה ממנו קודם שעלה לירושלים חוזר וזוכה בה מקבל שכך א”ל לעולם יהא שלך עד שאעלה לירושלים ומעכשיו ולאותו זמן שיקנה אותו ממנו נותנו לו מיהו דוקא בדאמר ליה מעכשיו אבל לא אמר לו מעכשיו לא קני (=הקונה) דכיון דקנינו בחזקה הוא וחזקה זו שהוא מחזיק עכשיו כבר כלתה לאחר שקנאה ממנו הוה ליה כמשוך פרה זו ולא תקנה לך אלא לאחר ל’ יום דאי לא קיימא ברשותיה לאחר ל’ יום לא קני הכא נמי כיון דאותו קנין שני לא חייל מהשתא אלא לאחר שיחזור ויקנה אותה ממנו וההיא שעתא כבר כלתה חזקה זו ואי אפשר לו שיקנה מיהו כי אמרינן דכל היכא דלא א”ל מעכשיו לא קנה.

He writes that if Reuven stipulated that the act of acquisition or possession of land taking place now would have legal significance only from the moment he goes up to Jerusalem—that is, the legal effect of the acquisition would not begin at the moment of the acquisition or possession but at some future moment—then no acquisition takes place at all. The field is not acquired by Shimon, neither now nor when Reuven goes up to Jerusalem. The Ran explains this case with the concept of “kaltah kinyano.” His claim is that once the act has been performed there are only two possibilities: either the result occurred (the legal effect was imposed) immediately upon performance of the act, or—if there is some problem—then nothing happened at the time of the act. But it cannot be that after the act was performed nothing happened, and suddenly at some later time the acquisition will be imposed out of nowhere. Such “hocus-pocus” is impossible because the act that could generate the legal effect has already concluded and is no longer in the world. Just as after I sold a field to Shimon I cannot, a week later, come back and say I cancel the sale. Once the act has concluded it is fixed, and its consequences are no longer accessible to me. In other words, for something to happen at some future moment, an act must be done at that future moment. It cannot occur by virtue of an act already done in the past that has concluded. Again, this too is apparently connected to the ontic conception of halakhah (though not necessarily). After facts have been established and created, that is the reality. There is no way to touch a fact without doing another act (with the parties’ consent, just as such consent was required in the original act). The Gemara on the following page in Nedarim (29a, the sugya of Bar Pada) writes that inherent sanctity (kedushat ha-guf) does not lapse by itself; that is, a legal effect does not change without an act.

If we now return to conditions, without the Torah’s innovation it would seem that a stipulation would be impossible. A condition attempts to make a change in the results of an act long after it has concluded. That cannot happen, for “kaltah kinyano.” In Batei Rivka, in her article on the annulment of oaths, the author noted this problem with respect to vows and oaths as well. Without the Torah’s innovation that a vow can be undone, it would not be possible—precisely because of “kaltah kinyano.” (Here too the explanation is uprooting retroactively, i.e., reverse causality along the time axis. See Shiurei Rabbi Shmuel, Makot §415, which compares the mechanism of “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea” in vows and in conditions.)

One more remark. In a comment to the previous column, the writer “Ha-Shelita” noted that later authorities explain the difficulty in conditions as the impossibility of imposing a halakhic effect “in two directions” (i.e., that it will apply if A occurs and will not apply if B occurs). I do not think this explanation stands on its own. That itself requires explanation: why should it be impossible to impose an effect in a bifurcated manner? Simply put, the explanation is one of the two I brought here.

Back to the Torah’s Innovation Regarding Conditions

In any case, we arrive at the conclusion that without the Torah’s innovation we would not know that one may stipulate—either because there is reverse causality or because “kaltah kinyano.” Therefore the Torah innovates the possibility of a condition. My claim is that this innovation is embedded in the structure of the chapter. We saw that after the chapter describes the parties’ rationale and interests, it devotes another paragraph to describing the mode of implementation. This is not just repetition in order to recount what happened. The Torah wants to teach us that there is indeed a way to implement that rationale. The way to do so is the stipulation, and the Torah innovates that a stipulation is indeed possible despite the problems of “kaltah kinyano” or reverse causality. It is no wonder, then, that for a stipulation to be valid it must be made in a very specific formula: in accordance with the rules of conditions. Only thus can a reverse causal mechanism be created. If we do not formulate the condition in such a way, the Torah’s innovation does not apply, and the condition cannot be created. If so, the parties’ will cannot be realized (even though it is clear that this is their will).

In other words: the Torah innovates that when a person makes a condition, a mechanism is created that accompanies the legal effect until the moment the condition is fulfilled or not, and therefore the acquisition does not conclude (it is not “fixed”). Both parties are still in the execution stage of the act until the moment the condition is fulfilled or not; therefore it is still possible to change the results of the past act. Implicitly, the claim is that when a person makes a condition, an additional suspended “something” is created that accompanies this legal effect, and that allows us to still touch it, make changes in it, or uproot it at a future time after the act has ostensibly concluded. In Beit Yeshai, vol. I, §35, R. S. Fischer describes this pictorially: the stipulation creates a “demon” and a “destructive force.” The demon’s task is to hold the legal effect generated by the act so that it does not “land” upon the person or object, and the destructive force executes the stipulation. According to him, giving the bill of divorce created the legal effect of divorce, and the demon holds it hovering in the air. The moment the condition is fulfilled, the destructive force eliminates the demon and the effect “lands” with a great crash upon the woman. But if the condition is not fulfilled, then the demon destroys the hovering effect and the results of the act dissipate. These are, of course, figurative expressions meant mainly to illustrate the ontic dimension in both the legal effect and the stipulation upon it. One needs a mechanism that prolongs the act which created the effect until the stage of the condition, and that is what enables retroactive operation after the act has already concluded (because in truth it has not concluded).

We may now say that this innovation of the Torah depends on the person formulating the condition as the Torah requires. In any non-standard formulation, the Torah’s innovation is absent, and thus the condition cannot come into being. The Torah’s innovation applies only to a condition formulated according to the rules of conditions.

Further Clarification: What Exactly Is the Innovation in the “Parashat Tena’im”?

In principle there are two readings of the innovation in the “Parashat Tena’im” (in the fifth paragraph of the passage, as I showed in the previous column):

  • The possibility of making conditions is self-evident, as in any legal system. The passage comes to innovate that a condition is effective only if the rules of conditions are met. Without that, the condition does not apply. That is, the passage comes to be stringent, to say that although the possibility of conditioning is self-evident, halakhah invalidates certain formulations of a stipulation. The innovation is not the possibility of stipulating but rather that it is limited. The purpose of the passage is to innovate the rules of conditions. On this understanding, the innovation of the story of Gad and Reuben is a stringency.
  • The Torah comes to innovate the very possibility of making conditions. But this innovation is limited to a formulation that follows the rules of conditions. Here the Torah is lenient and innovates the very possibility of stipulating, albeit limited to the standard formulation. This is a (qualified) leniency.

The difference between the two possibilities lies in what the situation would be without the Torah’s innovation. Possibility A assumes that even without the Torah we would know logically that one can stipulate (just as any legal system allows conditions). Possibility B assumes that without the Torah we would not know that one can make conditions at all. Why, then, in other legal systems is it self-evident? For the reason described earlier: ordinary legal systems are built on conventions and are therefore concerned only with the parties’ intentions. If their intent is clear, there is no reason to limit their ability to realize it in a contract. But in halakhah, clarifying the parties’ intentions is not enough. Halakhah has ontic constraints and therefore does not necessarily allow the realization of certain intentions. Thus, without the Torah’s innovation, perhaps we would not even grasp the very possibility of conditions within halakhah. This means that if the Torah had not innovated the possibility of conditions and a person nevertheless made one, then even if his intentions are clear the condition would be void—either because one cannot act backwards in time or because one cannot act once the acquisition has concluded (“kaltah kinyano”). In any case, the upshot is that the Torah innovates that it is indeed possible in halakhah (if one formulates the condition properly, in accordance with the rules of conditions).

These possibilities may depend on how we understand the mechanism of conditions. If we are dealing with “igla’i milta le-mafrea,” then as we saw above, the possibility of a condition is a simple logical point (as among the nations). There is no reverse causality and no problem of “kaltah kinyano.” Indeed, if the condition is not fulfilled, it is clear that the stipulator did not intend to impose the effect, and therefore it truly does not apply. All this happens even without the Torah’s innovation simply because the legal effect requires the will of the one imposing it. The innovation of the “Parashat Tena’im” according to this view can only be a limitation on the possibility of stipulating—namely, that it is effective only when the condition is formulated according to the rules of conditions. This is View A, under which the innovation is a stringency. But if the mechanism of a condition is “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea,” then one must innovate even the very possibility of conditioning (otherwise the problems of “kaltah kinyano” and reverse causality arise). According to this understanding, the Torah innovated the very possibility of stipulating conditions, but here too it limited it to a formulation in accordance with the rules of conditions. Only with such a formulation does the innovation of conditions apply, and “you have only what was innovated.”

One can be precise from Gittin 75a–b and parallels in favor of the second possibility. The Gemara there discusses the following condition:

ת”ר הרי זה גיטיך והנייר שלי אינה מגורשת על מנת שתחזירי לי את הנייר מגורשת מאי שנא רישא ומאי שנא סיפא אמר רב חסדא הא מני רשב”ג היא דאמר תתן לו את דמיה ה”נ אפשר דמפייסה ליה בדמי מתקיף לה אביי אימור דאמר רשב”ג היכא דליתיה בעיניה היכא דאיתיה בעיניה מי אמר אלא אמר אביי הא מני ר”מ היא דאמר בעינן תנאי כפול והכא הא לא כפליה לתנאיה מתקיף לה רבא טעמא דלא כפליה לתנאיה הא כפליה לתנאיה לא הוי גיטא מכדי כל תנאי מהיכא גמרינן להו מתנאי בני גד ובני ראובן מה התם תנאי קודם למעשה אף כל תנאי קודם למעשה לאפוקי הכא דמעשה קודם לתנאי אלא אמר רבא משום דמעשה קודם לתנאי מתקיף לה רב אדא בר אהבה טעמא דמעשה קודם לתנאי הא תנאי קודם למעשה לא הוי גיטא מכדי כל תנאי מהיכא גמרינן להו מתנאי בני גד ובני ראובן מה התם תנאי בדבר אחד ומעשה בדבר אחר אף כל לאפוקי הכא דתנאי ומעשה בדבר אחד אלא אמר רב אדא בר אהבה משום דתנאי ומעשה בדבר אחד.

Without entering all the details of the sugya, I have underlined the two sentences from which this can be inferred. The Gemara states there, with regard to two of the rules of conditions (“condition before the act” and “condition and act concerning two different matters”), that since we learned the entire matter of conditions from the tribes of Gad and Reuben, it is clear that this was innovated only when the condition is formulated as it was there. “You have only what was innovated.” From the Gemara’s wording it is already clear that the assumption is that we learned the entire matter of conditions from Gad (not only the rules). And, of course, even in the substantive reasoning the Gemara brings we see that because the entire matter of conditions is learned from there, you have only what was innovated. This logical move depends on the assumption that we learned from Gad not only the rules but also the very possibility of stipulating—that is, a leniency, as in View B above.

Note on the Double Condition

In passing I will note that the Gemara above mentions another of the rules of conditions: that the condition must be doubled (tenai kaful). But regarding this rule the Gemara does not preface with “mikdi…”—i.e., it does not say there that since we learned the whole matter of conditions from Gad and Reuben, we must double the condition. Why is it that specifically for the double condition this phrasing does not appear? Perhaps because the need to double the condition does not stem from the learning from Gad and Reuben but from another source, or from logic.

Indeed, the Gemara in Nedarim 11a explains that this need stems from logic. Without getting into the details of the sugya there, I will cite the relevant line:

אי ר”מ לית ליה מכלל לאו אתה שומע הן דתנן ר”מ אומר כל תנאי שאינו כתנאי בני גד ובני ראובן אינו תנאי.

We see that R. Meir’s demand to double the condition stems from a logical consideration: from a negative you cannot infer a positive. Therefore, if one states only the positive or only the negative, we cannot know the other side of the condition. Hugo Bergman, in his Introduction to Logic, cites a student who noted that this distinction is rooted in a logical principle: when I say “If X then Y,” does it follow that “If not-X then not-Y”? Certainly not. If X is a sufficient condition for Y, this does not mean that “not-X” is a sufficient condition for “not-Y.”[1] For example, if a working fan is a sufficient condition for wind, does that mean that when it is not working there will be no wind? There may be wind from another source (natural breeze or another fan). Therefore R. Meir demands that each person double his condition.

There is room to discuss whether his intent is to say that this truly does not logically follow—that when a person says, “Here is your bill of divorce on condition that you do not drink wine,” it really is not clear that his intent is that if she does drink, then the divorce will not take effect. Seemingly that is indeed his intent. From the standpoint of interpreting his words and intent, this certainly seems so; therefore it is more reasonable that the rules of conditions require a formulation that proves this from the wording itself. This is not required to clarify the speaker’s intent but as a halakhic requirement of a proper formulation. If from the formulation itself the result does not follow logically, then even if the stipulator’s intent is clear, the condition is void. True, all this can seemingly be said only according to the view that the double condition is not learned from the story of Gad and Reuben. If this is not about clarifying intent, whence do we know that the speech must be self-containedly clear? Perhaps this derives from the very law of verbal articulation (hafla’ah). As with vows and oaths, speech is required for them to take effect; so too with conditions. And if speech is required, logic dictates that the speech must be self-evident.

I will note that some Rishonim write that where the matter is obvious to all (“what is in his heart and in everyone’s heart”), there is no need to double the condition (see Tosafot, s.v. Devarim she-ba-lev, Kiddushin 49b). But this does not necessarily contradict what I argued here. Where the matter is obvious to any observer, it is as if it were stated explicitly. But where the matter is “clear,” yet does not emerge with complete clarity from the formulation and context, then in practice it has not been said, and therefore the rules of conditions have not been met. In such a case the condition is void. This still requires study.

This matter is disputed among the Rishonim. In the Nedarim passage cited we saw that R. Meir’s position derives from the logical principle that from the positive you cannot infer the negative. But in the Rambam it appears he did not rule this way. In KoSh, Bava Batra §437–8 (and also vol. II §42), it is demonstrated that according to the Rambam this has no connection to the dispute whether “from the positive you infer the negative,” but is rather one of the rules of conditions learned from the conditions of Gad and Reuben:

תלז) [דף קלב ע”א] עוד תירץ שם הרשב”א דכיון שלא התנה כהלכתו גלה דעתו שאינו מקפיד עיין שם, אבל מדברי בעל המאור פרק ב’ דביצה משמע דגזה”כ הוא אם התנה שיהא כהלכות תנאי, וכן משמע מדברי המ”מ פ”ו מהל’ אישות בשם הגאונים הראשונים, וקשה דגבי חולין לא אוכל לך מייתי בגמרא נדרים י”א פלוגתא דר”מ ורבנן בתנאי כפול דפליגי אי אמרינן מכלל הן אתה שומע לאו, ומאי ראי’ דלמא ר”מ ס”ל נמי מכלל הן אתה שומע לאו, ומ”מ בעי תנאי כפול מגזה”כ דומיא דב”ג וב”ר, וד”ז שאלתי את כ”ק מ”ר הגר”ח הלוי זצ”ל, והשיב דפלוגתא דמכלל הן אתה שומע לאו היא אם הלאו נכלל בלשון ההן, וא”כ כשאומר ההן לחוד הוי כאילו אומר ההן והלאו, וממילא הוי כפול, ואידך מ”ד ס”ל דאף דאנו מבינין גם את הלאו מדבריו, מ”מ אינו בכלל לשונו ולא מיקרי פירש את הלאו, ולא הוי דומיא דב”ג וב”ר, ולענין נדר בעינן לבטא בשפתים, ומשו”ה תלי בפלוגתא הנ”ל עכ”ד.

תלח) [דף קלב ע”א] אבל בחידושי הר”ן גיטין מ”ו גבי המוציא אשתו משום אילונית דלר”מ בעינן דכפליה לתנאיה, הקשה מ”ש תנאי כפול מכל דיני תנאים דלא בעינן הכא, ותירץ דבתנאי דלעבר לא בעינן דיני תנאי כלל, ומ”מ ס”ל לר”מ דבעינן כפילא משום דמכלל הן אי אתה שומע לאו, והכא ליכא טעמא דלבטא בשפתים, ומוכח דלר”מ אין אנו מבינין כלל מדבריו את הלאו, ולפי”ז צ”ל דהא דבעינן תנאי כפול לר”מ, הוא מפני שני טעמים א) דבעינן דומיא דב”ג וב”ר כמפורש במשנה קידושין ס”א ב) דמכלל הן אי אתה שומע לאו, וכן מוכרח מהא דס”ל לר”מ דבעינן תנאי כפול גם בע”מ והתם לא ילפינן מב”ג וב”ר לשיטת הגאונים, דכמעשיו דמי, והרמב”ם פוסק כר”מ בהא דבעינן כפילא מדין תנאי דומיא דב”ג וב”ר ובאידך פלוגתא פסק כר”י, דמכלל הן אתה שומע לאו, היכא דלא בעינן דיני תנאי, וכן כתב בפירוש המשניות פרק האומר דלא קיי”ל כר”מ בהא דבעי כפילא בע”מ, וכן במוציא אשתו משום אילונית ובחולין לא אוכל לך פסק דלא כר”מ, דר”מ ור”י הלכה כר”י, לבד בדיני תנאי פסק כר”מ, משום דאתקין שמואל בגיטא דש”מ כוותיה.

From the first passage it appears exactly as I argued: because of the logical principle that from a negative you do not infer a positive, then even when the meaning of the condition is “clear,” the condition must be doubled. The logical principle underlies the learning from Gad and Reuben (were it not so, we would not learn it from there; I remind the reader of Tosafot in Ketubbot regarding chalitzah, cited in the previous column, which explains that we do not learn from Gad what lacks internal logic). In other words, because R. Meir holds that from the positive you do not infer the negative, it follows that a statement of the positive alone does not include the negative in its wording. Therefore, even if the stipulator’s intent is clear without doubling the condition, one must still double it.

However, according to the Rambam, the double condition is indeed learned from the story of Gad and Reuben, since he rules like R. Meir and at the same time rules that “from the positive you do infer the negative.” Seemingly, in his view there is a complete disconnect between the logic and the learning from Gad and Reuben. But even this is not necessary. Perhaps his claim is that logically you do not infer the negative from the positive, and therefore we learn from Gad that the condition must be doubled. Yet at the same time, with respect to a person’s intent, from the positive we do infer the negative.

Implication: The Condition Is Void but the Act Stands

The Gemara in Ketubbot 56a brings a dispute between R. Meir and R. Yehudah whether one can condition against what is written in the Torah in matters of money:

דתניא האומר לאשה הרי את מקודשת לי על מנת שאין ליך עלי שאר כסות ועונה הרי זו מקודשת ותנאו בטל דברי רבי מאיר ר’ יהודה אומר בדבר שבממון תנאו קיים.

According to R. Yehudah, in monetary matters one may condition against what is written in the Torah, and so is the halakhic ruling.

Tosafot (s.v. Harei zo) there raise a difficulty:

הרי זו מקודשת ותנאו בטל – ע”כ בדכפליה לתנאיה איירי דאמר לה אם אין ליך עלי שאר כסות ועונה הרי את מקודשת ואם לאו אל תהי מקודשת מדקאמר לקמן דטעמא דר’ מאיר דתנאו בטל משום דמתנה על מה שכתוב בתורה ואי לא כפיל לתנאה תיפוק ליה דתנאו בטל לרבי מאיר משום דבעי תנאי כפול כדאמר בהאומר (קדושין דף סא. ושם).

Up to this point Tosafot demonstrate that the case assumes the groom doubled his condition. But in light of that, the ruling here is very difficult:

ותימה אם כן אמאי היא מקודשת הרי התנה בפירוש שאם יהא לה עליו שאר כסות ועונה שאינה מקודשת.

If he conditions against what is written in the Torah, his condition is void. What does that mean? That she is betrothed without the condition (the condition is void and the act stands). Tosafot argue that even if such a condition is nonstandard, we should have voided the betrothal, not the condition. On the branch that he undertakes to provide food, clothing, and conjugal rights, he did not intend to betroth her at all—so how can we rule that she is betrothed despite his not intending to? R. Yehudah as well agrees that in principle a condition is void if it contravenes what is written in the Torah; he only holds that in monetary matters this is not considered conditioning against the Torah and the condition therefore stands. In other words, Tosafot’s question challenges both R. Yehudah and R. Meir. Essentially they are challenging the entire law of conditioning against what is written in the Torah (for R. Yehudah—only in prohibitions; for R. Meir—even in monetary matters): how can it be that the condition is void but the act stands, when if the condition is not met he did not intend the act to stand? Can we determine that the woman is betrothed to him without his wishing to?

We saw above that apparently there will be a difference here between the “igla’i milta le-mafrea” conception—under which it is clear that on the branch that the person did not intend, the act certainly will not apply—and the “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea” conception, under which this is not at all obvious. Indeed, among the Rishonim a view is brought here that says this explicitly.

Tosafot ha-Rosh here (and the marginal Tosafot Yeshanim) cite R. Tam’s explanation:

ואומר ר”ת דהיינו טעמא דכל תנאי שאדם עושה להתנות על מה שכתוב בתורה אין דעתו שיהא התנאי קיים אלא כמפליג בדברים בעלמא בדרך ליצנות ודמיא להא דגיטין הרי זה גיטך על מנת שתרדי לתהום שתעלי לרקיע וכו’ אינו אלא כמפליגה בדברים וכשר.

He explains that such a condition is void because the stipulator did not truly intend it. It is like a person exaggerating in speech (a condition impossible to fulfill). Such a condition is void because he did not seriously intend it (according to him, this appears to be logic, not something learned from Gad and Reuben). Note well: he claims the stipulator did not seriously intend the condition (not the act); i.e., his intention was to betroth in any case. His assumption is that if indeed the stipulator did not intend to impose the act if the condition is not met, then it would be impossible for the act to take effect. This is precisely the “igla’i milta” conception, which aligns with View A above (that conditions would have been known logically, and the innovation of the Gad and Reuben passage is a stringency).

But further in Tosafot (and in Tosafot ha-Rosh) they cite R. Yehudah’s answer:

ואור”י דאי לאו דילפינן מתנאי בני גד ובני ראובן ה”א דשום תנאי אינו מבטל את המעשה ואפילו לא יתקיים בסוף המעשה קיים והשתא דילפינן מהתם דמהני תנאי לבטל המעשה אמרינן דדוקא כשאינו מתנה על מה שכתוב בתורה דומיא דבני גד ובני ראובן שלא התנו על מה שכתוב בתורה.

R. Yehudah argues that the law of conditioning against what is written in the Torah is learned from the story of Gad and Reuben, but he writes that even the very ability to condition is learned from there. It appears he understands the Torah’s innovation in the Gad and Reuben passage as View B above (unlike R. Tam): that the passage innovated the ability to make conditions—a leniency. I noted that this fits the “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea” conception. We saw that this also emerges from the sugya in Gittin 74b.

R. Yehudah is essentially saying: the story of Gad and Reuben teaches us the very ability to stipulate. Without that innovation, conditions would not be valid. But this innovation is qualified, for a valid condition is only one formulated properly. Only with respect to such a condition was the innovation—that a condition can uproot an act (backwards in time, after “kaltah kinyano”)—said. What happens if a person makes a nonstandard condition? In such a case the condition is void and the act stands. How does this resolve the difficulty? Why should the act stand—after all, he did not intend to betroth her if she is entitled to food, clothing, and conjugal rights?

Later authorities (e.g., KoSh ad loc., and many others) explain that in order for a condition to operate, a person intends to condition according to the rules the Torah sets: namely, to impose the act in any case, and to create a condition that will uproot the act if the condition is not fulfilled. In any other form he cannot succeed in realizing his will (because halakhah—unlike ordinary legal systems—does not allow such a will to be realized due to legal constraints of reverse causality, etc.). That is, when a person conditions, he thereby demonstrates that he intends to impose the legal effect in any case, and in parallel his stipulation creates a condition (the “demon,” the “destructive force”) that ensures the effect will be uprooted if the condition is not met. This is the only mechanism that will enable him to realize his will (to impose an effect in a bifurcated way). But an error occurred here, for he did not formulate the condition properly. What happens then? The act is imposed in any case—for that is indeed what he intended—but the destructive force and the demon that could uproot it if the condition is not fulfilled do not come into being. Therefore the result is that the act stands in any case and the condition is void. Note that this is true even though the stipulator’s desire was that in such a scenario the betrothal not take effect (since the condition was not fulfilled). Due to halakhah’s constraints he is nevertheless forced, despite his will, to impose the betrothal in any case, and his mistake in formulating the condition caused this to be fixed.

This sharply expresses the distinction I made in the previous column between rationale and legal-halakhic implementation. According to R. Yehudah, the groom’s rationale and interest are clearly that he does not want the betrothal if she has claims upon him for food, clothing, and conjugal rights. But the contract capable of realizing this obligates him to betroth in any case (and to create a condition that can uproot the act if the condition is not fulfilled). The outcome is contrary to his interest as it appears in his rationale, but it does conform to his legal will (i.e., the contract that implements the rationale and to which he agreed).

Note that all this is a direct result of the paragraphing in the story of Gad and Reuben. We saw that the Torah innovated the “Parashat Tena’im,” implying that without this innovation conditions would not be valid in halakhic law. From this it follows that if a person stipulates in a nonstandard way, the Torah’s innovation—that the condition can uproot the act—has not been said; consequently, the act remains in force: the condition is void and the act stands. This is so even though it is crystal clear that the stipulator wanted the act itself to be void in such a case (since the condition was not fulfilled).

A Note on the Rambam’s View

In the comment referenced above to the previous column, the writer asked why the Rambam holds that in a “from now” condition (me-achshav) the rules of conditions are not required. For there too the person is imposing a legal effect in a bifurcated way, and therefore the Torah’s innovation is needed; and as stated, that innovation applies only if the person formulates the condition properly. If so, when he did not formulate it properly, the result should be that the condition is void and the act stands, both in a “from now” condition and in an “if” condition. Yet according to the Rambam, in a nonstandard “from now” condition, the condition stands—i.e., if the stipulatee does not fulfill it, the act is void.

According to the approach developed here, we can explain that the Rambam understands a “from now” condition as operating via “igla’i milta le-mafrea,” not “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea.” We saw that under the “igla’i milta” mechanism, there is no need for the Torah’s innovation, for the condition’s validity follows from logic. Here there is no problem of “kaltah kinyano” and no reverse causality, and thus a condition would be valid even without the Torah’s innovation (as assumed under View A above). Therefore there is no need to formulate the condition in a standard form. All that is required is clarifying the parties’ will. We saw that this is apparently also R. Tam’s position. R. Yehudah, in contrast, apparently holds that a “from now” condition operates via “mi-kan u-le-haba le-mafrea,” and thus, according to him, even there the rules of conditions are required.

So far we discussed the “from now” condition. What about an “if” condition? We saw in the previous column that according to all Rishonim—both the Rambam and those who disagree with him—an “if” condition, which applies prospectively, requires the rules of conditions (their dispute concerns the “from now” condition). Seemingly here there is no problem of reverse causality, for the legal effect applies only from the time the condition is fulfilled and not retroactively. So why, in an “if” condition, must one specifically use the standard formulation? In Beit Yeshai it is explained that even in an “if” condition (and, according to the Rambam, specifically there) one must create the “demon,” for the act has already been done; how will the legal effect apply at the time the condition is fulfilled? In my terms: although there is no problem of reverse causality here, there is a problem of “kaltah kinyano.” Therefore, here all agree that a standard formulation according to the rules of conditions is required so that the Torah’s innovation will operate. The proper condition creates the “demon,” i.e., the mechanism that enables us to alter the situation after the act has already been done.

[1] It does imply that “not-Y” is a sufficient condition for “not-X.” This is the rule of denying the consequent.

18 תגובות

  1. If the reason that a condition is an innovation is because “her daughter-in-law bought it,” why didn’t the early writers distinguish between a condition of buying money, for example, in which case there is no such disadvantage and it would be useful even without the legal provisions of the conditions?
    Rambam, Divorce, Part 5, 11-12, writes that under the condition of “her mother,” the get does not need to be in her possession (and it seems that the condition is indeed useful against the disadvantage of her daughter-in-law buying it), although he does write that the get does need to be in the world. And it seems that the disadvantage of her daughter-in-law buying it does bother him, even though he makes a condition and the laws of the conditions (it is a condition of “if”) only that his reason is that the bill exists (perhaps from the kind of the one in Tos’ Yevamot Ch”3)
    Perhaps the Rambam believes the disadvantage of a retroactive contract only with the condition of “if” and with the condition of “from now” he believes that it is completely retroactive..?

    1. I didn't understand why buying money would be different.
      Regarding the need for the gett to be in her possession or in the world, it is because the condition extends the act until the moment the condition is fulfilled and then there must be a gett in the world.

      1. If the novelty of a condition is that it solves the problem of the bride price, then in ways that do not have the disadvantage of the bride price, such as in the purchase of money that is subject to a lien on the property, and in other purchases that do not have the disadvantage of the bride price, if he makes a condition, it will not be novelty, and so will it be useful even without the legal provisions of the conditions?!
        What I brought from the Rambam is that he also demanded that the get remain as it is, and this is in order to solve the problem of the bride price, and this is as you wrote, by extending the act, but if the condition does not have the disadvantage of the bride price, why should it be said that the act is over and that the application will still apply afterwards?

        1. What does it mean that the lien on the property exists? Do you mean to the one who transferred the money and has not yet performed a property transaction? I suggest you stop with the riddles and write what you mean.
          Regarding the get, because the condition is that the get must also be in the world and not just that the transaction still be performed. The transaction is performed on and through the get.

          1. You write that a condition is a new one because of one of two reasons, either because of the here and now, retroactively, or because of the inclusion of the purchase.
            And I am just commenting that the disadvantage of the bride of the purchase is only true in purchases that have this disadvantage, such as in the purchase of a draw, where it is said that the draw has ended, but in the purchase of money, for example, there is no disadvantage of the bride of the purchase (see Kiddushin S. and Toss Ketubot P. B. D. E. Ha). Therefore, a person who consecrates a woman in the purchase of money and makes a condition should not have the disadvantage of the bride of the purchase, and in any case, there should not be a new one in the condition, and therefore the condition will be effective even without the legal provisions of the conditions. And this is strange.

            (The question is conditional on the "if" condition, where you say that there is no problem of reverse causality, and so there is only the disadvantage of its own merit.)

            1. I didn't understand what you saw there. If he said from now on he buys, because it is a continuous act. But if he said later he doesn't buy. Then there is a completion of his purchase also in the purchase of money. Except that from now on he is a continuous act, and as if he finishes giving the money after a day.
              The difference between a withdrawal and money is that in a withdrawal it is not possible to define it as a continuous action, and in money it is because there is still the encumbrance and therefore as if the money still exists in the world and is given now. In a withdrawal there is only the act and it is already completed. In money because it exists now it is as if the action (giving the money) is also being done now.
              In a slightly different formulation in light of what I wrote to you above, if at all, then this ruling is parallel to the question of the existence of the get in the world and not to the question of the completion of his purchase. And we discussed these are different questions.

  2. What the Rabbi says regarding the ontological existence of the hallots and the realities derived from them
    I remember that we also reasoned in this why the additional mechanism of a final conditional clause is needed in the sense of something external that cancels the hallots as written here, because the moment a person does an action that is defined to apply hallots, it operates by the very fact that they did it, and the reason for its operation now is not the will of the owner but an autonomous metaphysical law, and therefore it does not belong to involve will in this mechanism.

  3. What about situations where a man consecrates a woman and he imposes a condition that does not meet the laws of the conditions, but the condition is for the woman's benefit and without it the woman would not have been willing to be consecrated? Does that also mean that the condition is null and void and the deed is valid?

    1. Clearly. Every condition in any contract that has two parties is a bilateral condition. It is like the wife's condition, by agreeing to the husband's condition. This is the basis for annulling the kiddushin on the basis of adatah dehki la ikdashah, which is essentially an implied condition.
      It is true that there is injustice here, because the husband made the mistake and the woman is the one who suffers. She should have clarified the language of the condition and made sure that he followed it.

      1. And if the husband does such a thing maliciously, that is, he sanctifies a woman whom they both know that without the condition she is not willing to be sanctified, and he takes advantage of her lack of knowledge regarding the laws of the conditions to sanctify her without the condition.

          1. Doesn't this halachic result seem a bit contrary to common sense to you? How is it possible to oblige people to abide by a contract that they did not intend to abide by in the first place (without the condition)?

            1. These are everyday actions. A person signed a contract and then it turned out that he had committed to something he didn't know about. They tell him that he should have found out before signing.

              1. Especially in this day and age, when every company makes you sign a lengthy agreement document that no one bothers to read, I understand that there are consumer protection laws that prohibit "unfair" terms in these agreements.

              2. True, but this is the exception that proves the rule. The Uniform Contracts Act. This is when there is a strong body versus a weak one and a contract that cannot be broken.

  4. Shalom Rabbi,
    Excuse me, but I think I understood the Rabbi in the vows differently than you, and I would be happy if you would explain my mistake and your reading.
    Rabbi there compares the laws of memonut to the laws of the dedication described there on the page and says that just as a person says that these plantings will be dedicated until they are cut down, they will be restored to their sanctity if he redeems them, until they are cut down. So too does Reuben who gives his field to Shimon until a certain time has passed - that he should go to Jerusalem - if Reuben buys it back from Shimon, the field automatically becomes Shimon's, due to the condition. Only after he goes to Jerusalem will the field return to Reuben's possession. (And in this case he divides between now and not later)

    The Rabbi wrote that Reuben is trying to give his field to Shimon after a certain time has passed - that he should go to Jerusalem. But this does not seem correct to the Rabbi.

    Another example of this is his discussion later, in the case where a third person - Levi - buys the field from Shimon, and sells it to Reuven, whether it returns to Shimon's hands due to the condition or not. The Rabbi claims that it is not a "dafskia".
    And further on in his words when he quotes Rabbi Moshe of Kortavi he brings a dissenting opinion that says that a condition does not work like that - and Reuven the gift that Shaddu would be purchased for Shimon, if Reuven bought Shaddu back from him, the field would not automatically return to Shimon due to the condition.

    The Rabbi will forgive me for the trivialities in the Rabbi's explanation, and I do not think that this affects the rest of the article but I did not examine it in depth.
    Thank you

Leave a Reply

קרא גם את הטור הזה
Close
Back to top button