New on the site: Michi-bot. An intelligent assistant based on the writings of Rabbi Michael Avraham.

Two Types of Modern Religiosity and a View on Traditionalism (Column 501)

With God’s help

Disclaimer: This post was translated from Hebrew using AI (ChatGPT 5 Thinking), so there may be inaccuracies or nuances lost. If something seems unclear, please refer to the Hebrew original or contact us for clarification.

The manifestos have concluded, the celebrations for the 500th column were canceled, and now we’re back on track.

Following the last column I received several responses and suggestions that prompted me to clarify a few points. I will focus here mainly on three: the first two concern my stance toward semi-political associations and platforms, and a fundamental distinction between my views and seemingly similar views that have been circulating in recent years in the marketplace of ideas under the heading of modern religiosity (and in fact, postmodern). At the end I will comment on the relation to traditional identity.

My stance toward rabbinic associations and organizations in general

More than once in the past I have been asked to join this or that rabbinic association. I’m very reluctant to do so, for several reasons. First, there is the question of the group’s identity itself. Do I accept its composition and aims, and do I trust its members? Are they truly Torah scholars, truly committed to halakha, and is their judgment acceptable to me? The Talmud (Sanhedrin 23b) says that the refined of Jerusalem would examine who sits with them at a meal, who signs a document with them, and who sits with them in judgment. When you join a beit din panel or any organization, you must be prepared for a situation in which your colleagues outvote you and you must sign their ruling even though you opposed it. That is possible only if you have full confidence in their level, integrity, and the fundamental direction of your colleagues’ thinking.

Beyond that, there is the question of the group’s self-definition as a “leadership” of this or that kind. To my mind this perpetuates the problem rather than solving it. You want leadership, and the leadership now is flawed and failing? No problem—let’s bring you another leadership. In my view, the very yearning for leadership is the problem. Sometimes it’s an illusion altogether that people are seeking leadership, and it is very convenient for self-appointed “leaders” to live within it. In the previous column (the manifesto) I wrote about the phenomenon of “notables,” as in an Arab village. If you want to move something in the national-religious public, you turn to a collection of “notables” (who, for some reason, call themselves “senior rabbis of religious Zionism”) and they arrange everything. In many cases this is done in the dark of one of these “notables’” offices (who, of course, were appointed to it by none other than themselves).

A third problem is that I’m allergic to a situation in which a group of people speaks collectively. In such a case, my personal positions are presented to the public by a spokesperson or by various committees of people, and not “from the horse’s mouth” itself. Anyone who wants to know what I think should ask me, not my spokespeople. Statements like “we think” or “Organization X believes that _” make me shudder. Exactly like the collective beliefs instilled in us in religious education (how many times have I heard questions phrased: “But after all, we believe that _”). This applies particularly to positions like mine, which are generally not really consensual and in many cases are not always understood correctly. Therefore I trust only myself to present them (and even that is not always justified).

On the other hand

Despite all of the above, I know that in order to promote agendas, organization is necessary. One person cannot really change anything. This is what people tell me again and again after the manifesto (the previous column) and in general. They suggest various platforms that can help advance the religious-modern idea, and I fully understand the logic in this. But this necessary compromise gives me hives, for the reasons I’ve detailed. I am certainly happy to sign this or that proclamation on a particular issue after I have examined it and found that I agree with its content. But I am not willing to be a member of an organization that speaks with one voice on a whole set of issues, and does so also in my name. Even if the organization publishes several opinions, it is still not certain that my opinion will be faithfully represented there (usually that is not the case).

I will not deny that this purism works to my detriment. A lone voice crying out in the wilderness cannot really change much, since it lacks significant specific gravity. But generally I do not aspire to defined goals and targets (the manifesto spoke about forming an identity, not creating a party or an institution), and therefore perhaps the problem is less severe. Ideas seep in their own way, and I believe in sending out “your bread upon the waters” in the realm of ideas. We should help processes emerge and advance, but we should not expect that we will be the ones to make the change. That is too pretentious. In particular if I see my goal as clarifying the picture and elucidating basic concepts and principles—that is, theoretical aims intended primarily to provide backing for the broader and more practical processes. There organization is less necessary, and in fact mainly harmful. At the implementation stages, indeed, there is no escape from various associations, but they should preferably be local and aimed at a very specific purpose.

Later in the column I will point out a fundamental distinction between my views and those similar ones circulating in the marketplace of ideas, and through it I will again illustrate what I have explained here: that joining various associations is problematic for me.

The “Beit Hillel” organization

The Beit Hillel organization is the natural candidate to advance these ideas. When it was founded they approached me as well, but I did not want to join, mainly for some of the reasons above (and a few more). Upon its founding its identity took shape, and already in its title we see “Attentive Torah Leadership.” My general impression (also from reading its materials and foundational declarations) is that its primary goal is to address the general public and present a moderate and inclusive Torah that is relevant to everyone. Ostensibly a lofty and exalted goal. Sanctifying God’s Name (kiddush Hashem) and preventing its desecration (hillul Hashem) are foundational values in halakha.

And yet, this trend is the exact 180-degree opposite of my own. I too strive for a liberal Torah and religiosity, and as such it will likely be more accessible to additional people and groups. Perhaps it will even lead to a kiddush Hashem and prevent hillul Hashem. But I have no goal whatsoever to achieve that. At most it is a side effect. I have no interest in “including” additional groups, or in currying favor with anyone. On the contrary, if my words find favor in the eyes of too many people, I examine myself sevenfold, because I likely erred somewhere. My proposals for revolutions and changes and for adopting modern and external values are based solely on the notion that this is the correct way to serve God. This is truth, not inclusion or an attitude toward other groups, conceptions, or individuals. I would say it even on a deserted island. If those motivations are rooted mainly in inclusion, or in kiddush and hillul Hashem (what is called in less polite language “ratings,” though here in a positive sense), I am rowing precisely to the opposite shore: austere truth in all its dignity. Kiddush and hillul Hashem are of course very important values, but they are not my motivation, because in my view in most cases they are not a correct basis for ruling or changing halakha. I would not touch even the tiniest halakhic “nub” out of a consideration that it will find favor with secular, traditional, or Reform Jews, or that it will “include” them. On the contrary, if it does find favor in their eyes, I would try to avoid it. I have no interest in including them.

It is true that halakha includes a trend of adopting rulings and interpretive methods that are accepted by the public and avoiding rulings that distance the people in the fields from the Torah. But to the best of my judgment this applies to the people in the fields who are obligated to halakha, not to groups that are not obligated to it.[1] And even then it must be done sparingly and with great discretion. The Torah is not a means to create social cohesion; it has its own aims, which are not the gathering and unification of the people of Israel. The commandments are intended to achieve ends of their own (what I have often called “religious values”), and if people do not understand that, that is no reason to forego achieving those aims. The unification of the people is a means toward those aims, not the other way around. Therefore I am emphatically against compromises, painful or otherwise, in order to include other groups.

Similar voices

In recent years, a number of voices similar to those I described have been heard. Rabbi Ido Pachter repeatedly argues (see his book Judaism on the Spectrum) that we should change the definition of Judaism to include more shades: starting with traditionalists and Mizrahim, continuing with Reform Jews, and ending with secular Jews. Recently he overreached and claimed that Haredim are not on the spectrum (conversion to Haredism is invalid). A similar though more moderate direction can be found in Rabbi Ronen Lubitch’s book Should We Go with the Streams?. So too with Dr. Elhanan Shilo (in his book Existential Judaism) and a few others. All speak, in different hues, about Jewish religiosity as a spectrum, and call to recognize this spectrum ab initio and include it all within the religious and halakhic framework. One could say that this is postmodern religiosity.

At times I receive approaches from these and other figures who see me as a partner to their conceptions, and indeed the similarity can be deceptive. But in my impression, all of them are driven by motivations entirely foreign to me. They are trying to propose a Jewish identity that is diverse and inclusive, that addresses groups beyond those obligated to halakha (I am careful with the term “Orthodoxy,” which I too do not accept as a necessary basis for halakhic obligation). Usually this comes with widening the canvas and offering halakhic and philosophical options broader than customary. In that sense I am with them. But, as noted, my motivation is different—and indeed the opposite.

For my part it is precisely important to know and sharpen who is with us and who is against us. Not in the sense of denouncing or attacking them (I have often written that if a person truly believes in his path, at most he is coerced by circumstance, certainly not wicked and not deserving of any denunciation), but to understand what is included in Judaism and what is not. For me, definitions matter—even if they are broader. I am against blurring and fuzziness and various spectrums, unless it follows from conceptual analysis (I have written more than once about fuzzy logic). Ambiguity is not a value, and therefore I have no aim to blur definitions or abandon them. I certainly aim to update and clarify them, precisely to be exact and not to blur. The fact that conceptual analysis usually leads me to broader definitions is a result (a side effect), but certainly not the motivation for my moves.

In summary, I believe in modern religiosity, whereas those conceptions are perhaps closer to postmodern religiosity (this is, of course, a rough generalization only to sharpen the point).

Two kinds of pragmatism

I believe I have already noted here a distinction between two kinds of pragmatism. Philosophical pragmatism, which I have often written against, subordinates the “is” to the “ought.” It determines truth by what is useful (and effectively assumes there is no truth or that we have no access to it). In this sense it shares the meta-conception of skeptical and narrative postmodernism, according to which there is no way to reach truth (though they are usually presented as opposites; see, for example, Gadi Taub’s The Dwarf Rebellion), but it proposes, because of this, to adopt the useful as a criterion for truth. The problem is that this is, of course, fabricated truth. You invent truth because that is what is useful to you, and in any case you have no alternative.[2] This is essentially turning the opium of the masses into a l’chatchila ideal. But truth owes you nothing, and there is no reason for it to coincide with what is useful.

There is another pragmatism, according to which the fact that something is useful is an indication that it is true. I do not see the logic in such arguments, unless perhaps one believes in the guiding hand of providence that ensures this (in some contexts evolutionary arguments might lead there). But at least it is consistent. If someone thinks the useful is an indication of truth, then it makes sense that he would choose the useful as a criterion for truth.

This distinction recalls the difference I pointed out with the approach of Beit Hillel and those like them. The spirit that blows through their words is pragmatic in the first sense (subordinating truth to usefulness. And again, we are speaking of what is spiritually useful, of course—not self-interest). Whereas I am perhaps willing to accept pragmatism of the second kind. Sometimes acceptance by the public is an indication that the approach is true. This brings me to a halakhic example.

A decree that has spread among most of the public

In the past I wrote here (I now found it in column 277) about the halakhic rule that a decree or enactment must spread among most of the public in order to be accepted. The Talmud determines that a decree that has not spread among most of the public is void. It is commonly thought that this is a kind of pragmatic compromise: indeed it would be proper to act thus, for that is what the beit din in its wisdom understood, but the people in the fields cannot uphold it and the Torah was not given to the ministering angels. One must take them into account and nullify the decree. I explained there that in my view the plain meaning is exactly the opposite. If the public does not accept the decree, it is apparently incorrect. Those who sit in the study hall or on the bench are detached from the world, and therefore they must receive feedback from the people in the fields. The latter correct the errors that stem from the scholars’ intellectual detachment. In such a case, acceptance by the public is indeed an indication of truth. This is pragmatism of the second, reasonable, and acceptable type.

But, as noted, this refers to the people in the fields who are obligated to halakha and strive to fulfill it. A public that in principle does not strive to uphold halakha—its non-acceptance of some halakha tells us nothing.

Let us now return to our discussion.

What about coalitions: is there a practical difference?

At bottom, the picture that all these groups present can be very similar to mine. They too speak of flexibility and of importing external values. But if I am right, then their motive is different—and indeed the opposite. They do this to a large extent in order to include and make the Torah accessible to others (“ratings,” albeit in a positive sense—multiplying love for the Torah and for the Holy One, blessed be He; still an instrumental approach), whereas I do this even if it will not include others—simply because in my view this is the correct way to act.

I will say more. It is possible, and even very likely in my view, that after I present many of them with the question, they will agree with my approach. But in my impression, the spirit that blows through their words is different. It may be that this manner of presentation is intended merely to point out the benefit and necessity of the approach, and not that this is necessarily its substantive basis (regarding which they might agree with me that it is a substantive value-based foundation and not merely various inclusions). It may also be that the very framing can change the conceptions, and I would be very pleased if that were so.

Seemingly, what I have described so far is only a difference in motives and motivations. The picture and the practical goals are similar. This means that there is certainly room for a coalition between my conception and such groups and ideas, since we are striving toward the same practical aims. Of course I do not see anything wrong with them. I simply disagree, and at bottom there is much in common.

However, another question now arises: is there also a difference in substance here? Will my practical picture be identical to the picture arising from those conceptions? My answer is no. The resemblance is far from perfect (and because of it, all sorts of people claim I am a fanatic Haredi and don’t understand where to place me on the religious map). I will illustrate this with a few examples.

First example: the status of women in the synagogue

The well-known ruling of the rabbis and rabbinic women of Beit Hillel regarding a female orphan reciting Kaddish has already drawn my critique, and I will not revisit it here. I will only note that I fully agree with their permissive ruling, but my motivation to permit it is not to ease women’s distress and enable them to express themselves fully in the religious sphere (a not inherently illegitimate rationale). My motivation is that there is simply no reason to forbid it. Therefore I would not need any halakhic source to permit it (that was the main criticism I made of them there). There is simply no reason to prohibit it. Therefore even if women were not in distress, I would tell them to say Kaddish. Conversely, if there were a halakhic problem here, then even if they were in distress I would not rule that way (sometimes there is room for leniency in exigent circumstances, but I won’t go into that here. I’m speaking about the principled approach).

I will add that I am not familiar with an organized and official ruling from them on women reciting the Sheva Berakhot at a wedding (there are responses, such as this one by Rabbanit Chana Godinger), or on women’s Torah reading and aliyah (though see here an anonymous essay from their site). I estimate that issuing such a permissive ruling is more difficult, if only for fear that it will be perceived as an excessive leniency (Reform-like). In my view, Torah reading is plainly permitted and does not require too much argumentation. An aliyah to the Torah should, in my view, also be permitted. As for the wedding blessings, there is room to permit (though here halakhic work is needed). All of this, in my opinion, is indeed permitted. In some cases it is not because of women’s distress but because there is no reason to forbid. And in topics where there are sides to be lenient and to be stringent, there it is more appropriate to use the consideration of distress and need.

Second example: conversion

The same applies to conversion (see on this in column 469). I have often been asked how my stringencies in conversion (I see no place for any compromise regarding acceptance of the commandments. One who did not accept the commandments seriously and intentionally at the time of conversion is a full gentile, even if the beit din that converted him thinks otherwise)[3] accord with my leniencies in other areas. Why don’t I understand that we must be lenient here to solve severe social problems and ease people’s distress? My answer is that I do not “stringent” or “lenient” in halakha; I infer what seems to me correct. Sometimes that yields leniency and sometimes stringency. This is one of the differences between an approach whose aim is inclusion and kiddush Hashem—which generally tends toward leniency—and an approach that strives for halakhic truth in the given circumstances—which may arrive at conclusions of leniency or stringency.

I would never conceive of being lenient in conversion because there are social problems in the state. Secular people here created a severe problem with the deliberate import of hundreds of thousands of gentiles (as Rabbi Peretz of Ra’anana, who served as Interior Minister, rightly argued, and for which he took flak from all ends of the political spectrum and most ends of the religious spectrum), and now halakha must find ways to kosher the unkosher? Halakha is not an instrument for solving social and political problems. Halakha operates according to its measures and modes of conduct, interpretation, and ruling. The resulting consequences the society and the state must either swallow or vomit up—and best of all, ignore (separate religion from state). But that is a problem for the state, not for halakha.

Indeed this is a bill and its receipt attached. Alongside the stringency in requiring acceptance of the commandments, I propose (see in the column cited) a picture that greatly eases the definition of the acceptance of commandments required in conversion. In my view, it is sufficient that the convert understands that the system obligates him (and that he will be punished if he transgresses it). There is no need for an intention to actually keep the commandments, and certainly no need for actual observance. Without entering the claim itself, I will say again that here too I do not do this to ease someone’s burden or to solve anyone’s distress. “He who is in pain should go to a doctor” (Bava Kamma 46b), meaning: if it hurts you, see a physician (not a rabbi). I simply think that conceptual analysis shows that this is truly the correct halakhic picture. In principle it is correct even in a world that is entirely conservative Haredim who are punctilious about every jot and tittle, living and acting within a Jewish halakhic state à la the Taliban. In my view, one who does not act thus turns a kosher Jew into a gentile, and one could even say that there is here an excessive leniency (he exempts a kosher Jew from all the commandments).

Third example: the attitude toward traditionalism

It is very common to assume that there is an interest in bringing traditionalists closer and viewing them as part of the religious public. After all, they have a warm corner in their heart for halakha and Torah; they respect the rabbis and the Torah, but are a bit weak in observance. I think the attentive leadership aims, among other things, at this public. By contrast, I have written more than once that to me a traditionalist is far worse than an atheist. The traditionalist knows his Master and rebels against Him (does not observe halakha), whereas the atheist is entirely coerced by circumstance (a “captive infant”). I have no interest in including traditionalism, creating a “religiosity spectrum” that speaks to it, and certainly not one that recognizes it.[4]

Of course it depends which traditionalist we are speaking about. I refer here to a traditionalist who is aware of his religious and halakhic obligation, but it just doesn’t suit him at the moment. He cuts corners and drives on Shabbat to a soccer match after prayers, turns on the TV, and the like. That is unlike a person who fails occasionally because he cannot hold out. Such a person is not a traditionalist but a religious person who failed. Traditionalism is defined as a fixed and systematic mode of conduct, not as a local failure. There are, however, other kinds of traditionalism: those who do not really accept the full scope of halakha but see it as a kind of folklore, atmosphere, culture, and the like. In my view these are not traditionalists but secular people with folklore of a religious hue (like bringing first fruits, or alternative kibbutz-style holidays). They do not accept the authority of halakha, but see it as a charming family tradition worth preserving. It may even be dear to their hearts emotionally, but so long as there is no conception that this is binding truth, we are speaking of secularity (that is, a conception not obligated to halakha).[5]

Here too this is an example of a stance not aimed at including other groups or at leniency, but at striving to reach halakhic and conceptual truth.

I will now take the opportunity to address one of the responses to my manifesto, since it relates indirectly at least to my words above about traditionalism. The attitude toward traditionalism reflects, deeply and fundamentally, the distinction between the two conceptions I have described so far.

Implication: a critique I received of the manifesto

Unfortunately I am not on Facebook, but someone sent me a critique of the manifesto that was posted on the site’s Facebook page. I would like to take the opportunity to respond to it, because through it I will illustrate the attitude toward traditionalism and its connection to the distinction I made above.

Assaf Leibovitz writes there as follows:

Indeed an interesting analysis, though it lacks another dimension of analysis, namely, the traditional identity. In my view it is the third identity, with an emphasis on its religious-ethnic and class context. Your basic assumption is that if a person says he is a liberal and thinks he is a liberal, then he is indeed such. But since you have already used “false consciousness,” one could question this as well. The ethno-class dimension posits another option: a traditional, liberal, and Zionist Judaism in the formula proposed by Likud. This is a public that in practice acts in a liberal and modern manner on issues of women, LGBT, the IDF, and more, alongside a national and traditional Jewish faith-based outlook.

The fact that liberal religious Jews do not see in this identity an obvious intuitive ally, and that it is precisely the hardalniks who claim ownership of it, proves that ethnicity, class, and habitus carry great weight in political organization. In addition, this indicates that liberalism is an elusive concept and that racism, separatism, and intolerance can also exist in a liberal religious space (cf. many towns and kibbutzim). This is also the reason why the modern-religious identity remains a small niche, and unfortunately this article, in ignoring the traditional identity as a real, concrete option for dialogue and partnership, proves that it will remain such.

And in response to Chayuta he writes:

Ignoring the traditional identity, which in a proper world should have been the obvious intuitive ally of liberal religious Jews, demonstrates that this is not just ideology. There is a great deal here of class and ethnicity and sociological belonging. That is why national-Haredim and national-religious Jews still feel they are the same sector despite the gaps between them. That is why Haredim will not see the hardalniks as part of them.

In short, I’m not fond of those who look at the system and explain to everyone why it is not behaving “properly” instead of understanding its deep internal logic—a logic that holds up a not-so-flattering mirror to liberal religious Jews. And what most drives me crazy is how someone who lived in Yeruham (!) for years could be blind to the identity that existed right next to him.

If I gather what emerges from his words in these two passages, there is here an accusation that my words (together with liberal and modern religiosity in general) are racist, because I did not place on the map the third or fourth identity of Mizrahi traditionalism (in his words: Likud voters. So who is the racist here?). How could my eyes have been blind to the identity that flourished right next to me in Yeruham?! “Wild, huh?”

More on matters of taste

Since Assaf has shared his taste (whom he is and isn’t “fond of”), I will allow myself to share mine. I am really not fond of professional victims (who sometimes professionally victimize others). Those for whom whatever you say or write will be interpreted as discrimination and racism—toward them or toward others. If you include traditionalism, you’re a racist (why didn’t you include Bedouins or secular people? Why do you address Mizrahim separately? And why do you attribute traditionalism specifically to them?). And if you don’t include them, you’re also a racist. You surely recognize this amusing and infuriating phenomenon.

Why am I not fond of them? Because victimhood fills their entire screen, and therefore they are unable to see anything as it is and address arguments on their merits. It does not occur to them that there are much simpler and more compelling reasons for the phenomenon before them, and they prefer to jump straight onto the trendy racism bandwagon and attribute everything to racism and victimhood. To see this, let us look a bit at Assaf’s holy words.

My response to his words

First, I truly wonder why he thinks the Mizrahi-traditional identity does not appear on my map. According to his own view, it does appear. That is precisely the third identity I speak of. For some reason, in his view it differs from the liberal identity I described, but he himself says that they are actually natural partners because:

This is a public that in practice acts in a liberal and modern manner on issues of women, LGBT, the IDF, and more, alongside a national and traditional Jewish faith-based outlook.

Well then, by his own lights this is exactly the third identity I spoke of. Interesting why he thinks I did not relate to it? Ah—because, with his penetrating eyes, he discerned that when I related to liberals I (even if I did not say so) meant only Ashkenazi liberals and not Mizrahi ones. Racist that I am. According to his view, it seems I should have drawn a dual identity map: Ashkenazi and Mizrahi Haredim; Ashkenazi and Mizrahi religious-Zionists; Ashkenazi and Mizrahi modern-liberals; traditionalists only Mizrahi; and likewise Reform and secular (who, in his opinion, are only Ashkenazi) whom, due to my racism, I did not include at all. Actually, why only such a division? What about Poles, Czechs, Algerians, Tunisians, Belgians, and more? And after all that, I am the racist here. “Wild, huh?”

So here is a free lesson in reading comprehension. My eyes were not at all blind to the traditional identity (which is not necessarily Mizrahi, certainly not in recent years). I know it well, and as I explained above, I even lament it and view it as worse than atheism (racist that I am). In my view it is not a religious identity, certainly not more than the Reform identity. I also did not include the Bedouin, the tropical-equatorial, and the Hindu identities in my map, if only because they are not part of the map of Jewish-religious identities. I likewise did not include the traditional identity because, as I explained above, in my view it is not part of that map.

But never mind—that would have required him to know my stance on traditionalists, and there is no reason he should. The larger problem is what emerges from his words even if he does not know my stance. If, in Assaf’s opinion, I should have included all the identities that are natural partners to my conceptions, there are far better candidates than the traditionalists: Reform and Conservative Jews (the latter are not, in my personal opinion, a separate identity) and secular Jews. If I do not want coercion and want to give equal treatment to everyone, who are more faithful partners to us than secular and Reform Jews?! And yet, for some reason, Assaf does not wonder why I did not include these two “religious” identities on my map. “Wild, huh?”

I have a guess as to why this happens to him. Apparently, in his view, secular and Reform Jews are Ashkenazi, and Ashkenazim by definition are not victims (as they used to say in Gush Katif: an Ashkenazi does not victimize an Ashkenazi). Traditionalists, on the other hand, in his view are Mizrahi, and therefore they are by definition victims. As I said: professional victims see built-in victimhood everywhere. A person is shown only what is in his heart. That, I think, is why he passes in silence over the former (Reform and secular), whom I did not include on the map, while protesting the latter (traditionalists), whom—according to his own view—I did include (for they are liberals). An upside-down world I have seen. I at least am comforted by the fact that I equally “discriminate” against Ashkenazim and Mizrahim. Equality is a candle to my liberal feet.

This is the not-so-deep internal logic of my words, and for some reason Assaf’s eyes were blind to it. But I must say that it does not at all drive me crazy, for I know well this blindness: the kind that finds blindness in everyone else but itself. It is a blindness that prevents one from discerning one’s own blindness and attributes it to others—“he who disqualifies, does so with his own blemish.” There are many examples of this among the arguments of professional victims and their helpers, and I leave that to you.

I will conclude with an apology to Assaf for allowing myself to give him a bit of a public thrashing. It’s just that the very typical arguments he raised call for it. So I extracted some sparks from them (well, that’s my Hasidic identity) and used them to sharpen my conceptions further.

[1] Of course there are cases where these concepts address gentiles, but generally it is not correct to change halakhot in order to receive proper treatment from gentiles.

[2] It reminds me of Peres’s immortal remark: what is their (the right’s) alternative?! He assumes that if there is no other alternative to peace, then one must choose the bad one. The option that there is no path to peace at all does not exist in the eyes of such an inveterate optimist. One may also recall here, lehavdil, Rav Kook’s saying about the superiority of failing in baseless love over failing in baseless hatred. There too I noted that best of all is to fail in neither.

[3] Of course, if the beit din thinks that factually there was acceptance of the commandments, that is a different situation. There, even if in my view there was no acceptance of the commandments, my view is nullified in the face of theirs.

[4] Incidentally, with regard to counting toward a minyan the relation is, of course, the reverse: a traditionalist of the type I defined here counts toward a minyan, since he believes in God and prays to Him, while an atheist does not (he is, in my eyes, akin to adding a potted plant to nine praying men).

[5] I will not enter here my claim that religious feeling and experience have no importance or value in themselves (except perhaps as an expression of conception and faith, which do have value). I have addressed this more than once in the past.

25 תגובות

  1. Shalom Rabbi
    First of all, I'm really glad you posted this post, because it really sharpens your approach compared to common “modern” approaches.
    I read your trilogy and I'm pretty familiar with your approach to ”modern religiosity”. However, your disagreement with conservative religiosity (in its “regular” manifestations, not the extreme ones) is still not entirely clear.
    I would really appreciate it if you could write a post detailing the fundamental points of disagreement, including examples of their practical application.

    1. There is a series of lessons that is still ongoing, on tradition, conservatism and innovation. I go into great detail there. See here on the website in the video lessons.

  2. You are right, but you want to be right or make a change, that is, you have a website where you write your opinion and no one can distort it. You can, together with a few rabbis, open an organization that is more or less in your line of thought, such as Rabbi Ofran, perhaps Rabbi Yehoshua Pepper from the CSA organization so that it will be a modern Haredi representative (whose articles the rabbi will read, he is a pretty serious person), Rabbi Sperber, Rabbi Haim Navon (although I am not sure that you are friends) It is quite strange that I am being sarcastic, I need to explain to the rabbi how to make connections. I do not mean to be rude, but the rabbi is welcome to pick up the phone and start working.
    Thank you

  3. What is modern about the notion that there is no need for Torah leadership? This was the method ‘in the days of the judges’!

    Greetings, the Levite Boy

    1. In the Book of Hebrews, the experience of generations of Rabbinic Judaism shows that neither "organizations" nor propaganda, and certainly not "slanders," succeed. He who creates a great Torah work succeeds, whether in scholarship, jurisprudence, or thought. When a path is outlined for many based on the written and transmitted Torah that deals with the renewed questions, then the things are accepted and leave an impression for generations.

      With greetings, from the

  4. This post should have been published as an appendix to the booklet.
    It is not a ‘voice calling in the wilderness’ as it is written, but, “a voice calling: In the wilderness, make straight the way of the ’, a highway for our God”.

  5. Two types of pragmatism –
    One – Taub's version -“. You invent truth because it is what is useful to you….”
    But the truth does not owe you anything, and there is no reason for it to merge with the useful.”
    In the last sentence there is an assumption that there is one truth, and therefore it does not have to merge with the useful.
    But if I define truth as useful to me – then it merges with the definition.

    “There is another pragmatism, according to which the fact that something is useful is an indication that it is true.
    If someone thinks that the useful is an indication of truth, then it makes sense that he would choose the useful as a criterion for truth.”

    And here Nietzsche's question becomes difficult – “Useful for what? ”
    If someone thinks that a certain ideology is “useful” and therefore true – then he too
    “invented the truth” like Taub (his definition of ”useful”).

    1. בקביעת 'מה ראוי לעשות?' האמת היא: 'מה עוזר?' says:

      In the 1st of Elul, 2019

      What helps? – Hello,

      In a factual question, the discussion is indeed ‘What is the factual truth’, but when we ask: ‘What should be done?’ We are not discussing what is there, but what will be useful. What will bring about the improvement of the individual and the public, because that is what we seek.

      With greetings, Yaron Fish”l Ordner

      And also in a factual scientific discussion, when we see that the ’machine is not working’ – it is worth checking whether we do not lack knowledge of the facts…

      1. And even when it is clear to us what is right to do, we still have the responsibility of how to make things accessible in an acceptable way, as Maimonides said that apples of gold need to be wrapped in silver in order to make them accessible to many. It is my responsibility to be one of the transmitters of the word and to pass it on from generation to generation.

        With best wishes, Hanoch Hanach Feinschmecker-Palti

        1. המודרניות מחייבת התחברות למעשים הדתיים says:

          On the 19th of Elul, February 2nd

          Modern man finds it difficult to act solely from an ‘acceptance of the world’ without internal identification. So the modern religious person has two choices: either to develop a ‘third identity’ that reduces and eases the burden of the mitzvot, or to delve deeper into the &#8217Torah’ and from that to understand what the will of God is and the values inherent in the mitzvot, and then to do them with desire, out of understanding and identification.

          With blessings, Hasdai Bezalel Duvdevani Kirshen-Kwass

          The attempt to reduce and ease the burden of the mitzvot does not really help, as the more a person fulfills the mitzvot out of a feeling of ‘burden’ His resentment towards the strict and the strict ones who do not support him has grown. Even the limited burden will remain an oppressive burden.

    2. This is not a problem. One can always say that a person invents his own premises. But I claim that they are the product of intuition and not invention. Obviously I cannot prove this, but clearly this is not a problem but at most a counter-statement.

  6. But then how do you explain the conflict between the Torah and moral values? Truth and utility are separated?
    (In your opinion, as I think you have often claimed, there is a conflict and that is fine. Of course, one can think differently - that what conflicts with the Torah is probably not really a moral value, neither true nor useful.
    Maybe I mixed up a few things here, I would appreciate clarification)

    1. I didn't understand the question. Why wouldn't they clash? Or is the clash related to my claims here?
      Actually, the clash question, I dealt with extensively in series of lessons on Halacha and morality, at the beginning of moves between the standing ones and also here on the site (column 15 for example).

  7. There's no problem with them clashing when they're presented as systems with different interests. But I couldn't figure out where the concept of 'truth' comes into play in this clash.

    1. On the 19th of Elul, May the mountains bear peace to the people

      There are conflicting values in moral values. For example, on the one hand, the law of justice demands that justice be served with the guilty and that a deterrent punishment be given to him that will prevent him and others from returning to his sin. On the other hand, the quality of justice itself demands caution in the laws of evidence, proportionality in punishment, and consideration for mitigating circumstances. And the quality of mercy adds and demands consideration for the good deeds of the sinner and his family members who may suffer because of him. And the quality of kindness demands that the sinner be given an opportunity to repent and make amends, for God desires the good of His creatures.

      This means: there is a “conflict” between moral values. A storm of righteous emotions here and there. Here comes the quality of truth. Which demands seeing the picture in its entirety and giving a balanced solution that will weigh all the just considerations and offer everyone their rightful place.

      Morality is stormy with emotions on the right and left, and the word of God ’ – this is a law’ finds a balanced response to the storm of emotions, a true and complete solution that takes into account all the considerations. The tendency to see only one side of the picture – deviates from the truth. Seeing the picture in its entirety is the truth in its entirety.

      With regards, Amitai Shelah Farhani

      1. And hills in righteousness,
        I have no problem with the fact that only intuition that is consistent with the law can be true.
        I didn't understand if the columnist confirms this.

        1. ההלכה קולעת את כל האינטואציות למארג שלם (לע"ם) says:

          Peace to all,

          For intuition reveals part of the truth, and halakha weaves and integrates the various intuitions into a fabric of complete truth, giving each intuition its proper place, the ‘order of the world’ in the words of the Maharal. Of course, this is not Ramada”a's opinion.

          With greetings, Afshar

  8. Halacha is not a tool for solving social and political problems. Halacha operates according to its own standards and methods of conduct, interpretation and ruling.
    Thus writes our Rabbi Michael Avraham.
    And how does this position differ from the position of Zechariah ben Avkolas?

    1. רבי זכריה בו אבקולס עשה את השיקול החברתי (למאוזר) says:

      On the 19th of Elul, February 2nd

      To Mauser, a very good greeting.

      I will leave it to him to represent Ramada's position, but Rabbi Zechariah ben Avkoles certainly made the social consideration, whether they say this or that.

      The sages made only the "political consideration", the fear of danger due to the king's order and wanted to allow, for the sake of piety, to sacrifice a disabled person or to kill the informer.

      Razva also made the social consideration. In a society polarized between classes that whine about halakhic meticulousness from one end. Between zealots who are ready to kill for every "thorn of knowledge" – There was a real fear that the sacrifice would be interpreted as reinforcing the atmosphere that was gluttonous in halakhic meticulousness, while the killing of the perpetrator would be interpreted as justifying killing on the "thorn of Yoda". After all, Bar-Kamza did not solemnly declare his intention to inform, and Rizaba, in his humility, did not want to be "suspicious of the righteous" and commit serious offenses due to a suspicion that had not been fully clarified.

      Rabbi Yochanan disagreed with Rizaba in his comment "Blessed is the man who is always afraid". In his opinion, it is the duty of public leaders to suspect the stunner of conspiratorial intent and to act accordingly. But there is a social price for creating such an atmosphere of suspicion, and Rizaba refused to accept it.

      Best regards, Nahorai Shraga Agami-Psisowitz

      1. You managed to defend him well.
        But the criticism of him regarding the ruling of halakhah – or the failure to rule on halakhah also appears
        elsewhere. See here halakhah
        https://he.wikisource.org/wiki/%D7%AA%D7%95%D7%A1%D7%A4%D7%AA%D7%90/%D7%A9%D7%91%D7%AA/%D7%99%D7%96

        1. גם שם דוגל רזב"א בערך הלכידות החברתית (למאוזר) says:

          To Mauser – Shalom Rav,

          Also in the Tosefta that you mentioned, the young Dogal Razva (who is not yet crowned as Rabbi) strengthened social cohesion, by avoiding entering into a situation that is controversial in both B and H. If the bones are placed on the table, Zechariah will have to ‘take a side’ publicly in the dispute, and therefore he found a brilliant solution: throwing the bones and shells ‘from his mouth straight into the bin’ without having to enter into a dispute.

          Rabbi Yossi, who was argued with, and he excels in his ability to make an explained and reasoned halachic decision – I believe that it is not the avoidance of halakhic controversy that will bring about social cohesion, but rather the reasoned decision that will bring the majority to embrace it, and the minority that disagrees to understand it, even if they do not agree. When one understands the reason of those who disagree, even if one does not agree, mutual understanding prevents the dispute from turning into hatred.

          According to Rabbi Yossi, also in the case of Kamtza and Bar Kamtza, there should have been a reasoned decision, which, being reasoned, would prevent the fear that “those with defects will say, ‘They are relatives’” or “they will say, ‘He is causing defects in the holy places.’” The decisive court will explain that here there was a situation of severe protection of life that must deviate from the rules, and the public will understand the reasons and not be swept away in inappropriate directions. When one knows how to explain and reason, social cohesion is strengthened, according to Rabbi Yossi.

          With greetings, Nashaf

    2. What is the matter with shmita for a khivita? What does it have to do with Zechariah ben Avkoles? There it talks about rejecting the halakhah due to considerations of fiqun or danger. I am talking about halakhic interpretation due to extraneous considerations.

  9. I don't remember such severe criticism of any other Tanna.
    Double criticism – from both Rabbi Yochanan and Rabbi Yosi.
    And what was the point of mentioning the destruction of the Temple in the matter of bones and fragments?
    And it seems that he threw it behind him – behind the bed – and not “straight into the trash”.
    And if, as you say, the dispute is about the ”tactics” that should be adopted, and Rabbi Yosi believes
    that it is possible to convince with arguments – why does he express himself in such an irrelevant manner
    towards Zechariah ben Avkoles?
    And what is the meaning of “humility” in choosing one tactic or another?
    But, I admit, your explanation is original. I have never heard it.
    And in a situation where the students of Beit Shammai “are stabbing a sword in the Beit Midrash” in order to
    determine a halakhah like them – it seems that even Rabbi Yossi's arguments will not help. In sins.
    Happy New Year Mozer (Mozer in the Moon)

    1. In B”d 2’ Balul P”b

      To Mazor (bringing Mazor) – Shalom Rav,

      There is humility and there is humility. There is humility that seeks to avoid controversy, as in the manner of Zechariah who threw the garbage behind him so as not to place it on the table and enter into a dispute in B”S and B”H whether to clear the garbage by hand or by shaking the table.

      And there is the humility of Beit Hillel who stand by their opinions and prevail precisely because of their humility that leads them to first change the words of the disputant. Hatam Sanfer explains that in this way the B&#8221H showed that they had internalized the arguments of the disputant against them, but that they had an appropriate response to these arguments, and therefore their words were accepted by most of their listeners.

      I added that Rabbi Yossi also deserved to have the halakhah ruled in his favor, for the same reason that was reasoned with him, his words are properly reasoned, with a full presentation of the system of considerations (according to the method of the B'Ha) and therefore they convince their listeners.

      Rabbi Yossi argues against the custom of Zechariah (who was not yet described as a 'Rabbi' at that time) to avoid debate, that this approach that he took even when he was a 'Rabbi', a leader to whom the public's eyes are fixed, led him (according to the Jerusalemite version) not to take firm action against the host of the banquet who expelled Bar-Kamza, as he feared that the host of the banquet was right and Bar-Kamza had pushed himself into a banquet to which he was not invited. And the Babylonian version (according to Rashi) suggests that Bar-Kamza may have cast the spell by mistake and not with malicious intent to inform.

      According to Rabbi Yossi, it is possible and necessary to take an unequivocal position. Clarify the sides of the debate thoroughly, and in light of the thorough clarification, you will be able to give a clearly reasoned decision that will be accepted by the public.

      With blessings, Naz’af

      That is perhaps why the codification of the B’Yi and the Shul’A (together with the glosses of the R’Ma) succeeded in becoming the cornerstone of every halachic discussion throughout the nation, because they clarified the variety of methods of the early scholars (in the B’Yi and the B’M) and established and justified their decision.

Leave a Reply

Back to top button