New on the site: Michi-botA wise assistant on the writings of Rabbi Michael Avraham.

Not in Heaven: A Look at the Rules (Tor 505)

With God’s help

Last Shabbat (Parashah Nitzavim) I discussed in synagogue the principle of "It is not in the heavens," which is based on a verse in our parashah. We have accepted that this verse prohibits relying on the heavens in deciding halakhah, and refers us to the decision of humans. I will begin here by discussing whether and how such a principle emerges from the verses, and then I will move on to comment on it and its relationship to the rules in halakhah and in general.

The verses

The parsha in which this verse appears ostensibly deals with exhortation to serve God (Deuteronomy 30:11-14):

For this commandment which I command thee this day is not strange unto thee, neither is it far off: it is not in heaven, that thou shouldest say, Who shall go up unto us from heaven, and bring it unto us, that we may hear it, and do it? nor is it beyond the sea, that thou shouldest say, Who shall go over the sea for us, and bring it unto us, that we may hear it, and do it? for the thing is nigh unto thee. It is very much in your mouth and in your heart to do it:

Simply put, the parsha seems to want to teach us the lesson of the Hindu parable of the Rabbi of Breslov. Do not think that you are too small to serve God and that the Torah is too sublime and high for you and beyond your reach. It is close to you and within your reach to fulfill it. As it is said: There is no despair in the world at all (except for the cases that exist).

But it seems that the Sages did not study the verses in this way. According to their view, there is a meta-halakhic principle here. Thus we find in the Gemara BM 55, in the act of Akhnai's oven:

That day, Rabbi Eliezer answered all the answers in the world, but they did not receive them. He said to them, "If the law is like my carob, it will be proven. The carob will be uprooted from its place a hundred cubits away. I told her, four hundred cubits away." They said to him, "They do not bring evidence from the carob." He returned and said to them, "If the law is like my water well, they will prove it." The water well turned behind them. They said to him, "They do not bring evidence from the water well." He returned and said to them, "If the law is like my walls, the walls of the house of worship will fall down." Rabbi Yehoshua rebuked them. He said to them, "If you are scholars who defeat one another in law, what is your nature? You did not fall because of the honor of Rabbi Yehoshua, and did not stand up because of the honor of Rabbi Eliezer, and yet you are still standing." He returned and said to them, "If the law is like my law from heaven, they will prove it." A voice came out and said, "What do you have with Rabbi Eliezer, whose law is like it everywhere?" Rabbi Yehoshua stood up and said, "It is not in heaven." Is it not in the heavens? Rabbi Jeremiah said, "The Torah was already given on Mount Sinai. We do not observe the voice of the Lord, who has already written it on Mount Sinai in the Torah, after many years of neglect." Rabbi Nathan said to Elijah, "What is the holy servant, blessed is he? He is in that place." He said to him, "How did you live?" And he said, "My son, my son, win!".

There was a halachic dispute between the Rabbi and his colleague and friend Rabbi Yehoshua and his younger friends/disciples, and even a Bat Kol that came out in favor of the Rabbi did not convince them. The rule that Rabbi Yehoshua relied on is taken from the verses above: "It is not in heaven," and from this he learns that one does not observe a Bat Kol but follows the majority. The legend ends with the fact that even the Blessed One smiled and said, "I have prevailed, my son" (meaning: I tried, but it did not work…).

How is this principle learned from the verses? On the face of it, this is a simple teaching, since the verses are not concerned with deciding the law at all, but with encouraging people to observe the Torah and alleviating their despair and despair. But a closer look at the verses reveals that the matter is not so simple.

In the two middle verses, the Torah is not content with saying that the commandment is not in heaven or beyond the sea, but also negates the statement "Who will ascend to heaven for us and bring it to us and make us hear it and do it" or "Who will cross the sea for us and bring it to us and make us hear it and do it." These additions are not consistent with the interpretation of the verses as an exhortation and alleviation of despair. If the verses were intended only to encourage us to keep the Torah, I would expect it to only write that it is not in heaven or beyond the sea but in your mouth and in your heart to do it. It is not far away but within us and within our reach. The despair that we cannot keep the Torah is not supposed to be resolved by sending someone to bring us the Torah. This is not a relevant solution to such a situation. The expression "you were amazed" also does not seem relevant if it is a difficulty. Such an expression speaks of a lack of understanding and intellectual distance. The same is true of the conclusion that the Torah is in our mouth and in our heart to do it. If it is a difficulty, then the problem is not in the mouth or the heart but in weakness and instincts.

From all these considerations, it seems that the interpretation of these verses is different. It seems that the Torah really came to deal with the feeling of doubt that can arise in us, that because of the despair that we do not know what to do (the Torah is wonderful than us, understanding it is not within our reach) we would expect someone to bring us the answers from afar, from heaven or across the sea (a voice, a prophet, the Holy Spirit). And so the Torah says that we should not expect this. Everything depends on us, that is, it is decided in our own mouths and hearts. The decision of what to do is left to human beings here on earth, and we should not expect decisions from heaven. I think that is how the Sages deduced their meta-halakhic interpretation from the verses themselves, and in my opinion this is not a demand or demand, but an interpretation that certainly fits well into the plain language.

Resolving a dispute in the "S" and "B"

In the issue of Eruvin 13b, we find a decisive verse in the controversy between the Hebrews and the Hebrews:

Rabbi Abba said, Samuel said, "For three years, the House of Shammai and the House of Hillel were divided. These say the same law as we do, and these say the same law as we do. A voice came out and said, 'These and these are the words of God, and the law is like the House of Hillel.' And since these and these are the words of God, why did the House of Hillel deserve to establish the same law as them? Because they were comfortable and humble, and their words differed from the words of the House of Shammai, and what is more, they prioritize the words of the House of Shammai over their words...

B.S. and B.E. were unable to reach a decision between them, so they needed a vote. This was the decision that went to B.E.past On the background and uniqueness of this controversy.[1] In any case, the conclusion of the voice is that it determined that the halakhah is according to Beit Hillel. This is the most definitive halakhic ruling in the history of halakhah, and from there on we accepted that "the words of B"S in place of B"H do not change" (Beitza 11b and parallels).

This is also true in the issue of Eruvin 6b. It begins with the baraita:

And who are the servants of material crowns, and will not you forever proclaim the law as the House of Hillel? And whoever wants to do according to the words of the House of Shammai does according to the words of the House of Hillel, does according to the words of the House of Shammai, and according to the words of the House of Hillel, a wicked man from the materials of the House of Shammai and from the materials of the House of Hillel, concerning whom the scripture says, "The fool walks in darkness, but is not like the House of Shammai, as a voice and as a voice, or

One should be consistent and follow a particular ruling, either B.S. or B.H. One should not even make material distinctions, meaning to be strict as if two conflicting opinions.

The Gemara now stops and complicates the baraita itself in its various aspects:

You said, "The law is according to the House of Hillel and Hadar," and you said, "Whoever wants to do what the House of Shammai says does so."

If the halakha is הבה, how is it possible that a person can choose to follow הבה? The Gemara offers three excuses.

The first:

I won't ask here before Bat Kol, here after Bat Kol.

This is before the voice of the Lord, the decision was made according to the will of God. But after the voice of the Lord, it is truly no longer possible to choose to follow the will of God.

The second:

And I heard a mother say, "Ha ha, after a daughter of a kol", And Rabbi Yehoshua said that she is not a mishgad in Bat Kol.

Even after the Bat Kol that was ruled, one can follow B.S. The baraita here does not follow the method of Rabbi Yehoshua (in the issue of the oven of Akhnai) who does not observe Bat Kol. This excuse implies that there is a dispute on the matter, and this baraita holds that there is no rule of "not in the perfume." Although according to the halakha, in the issue of B.M., it appears that Rabbi Yehoshua ruled, and therefore, apparently, according to this excuse, there is no obligation according to the halakha to rule as follows. This is quite puzzling.

The third:

And the mother of the most important thing is that all of this is forgotten, and the Amorites of the Philistines are divided, as is the dispute between the House of Shammai and the House of Hillel, not to worship because its voice is deaf and because its voice is deaf, nor according to its materials, because its materials are deaf, but either because its voice is deaf and because of its materials it is worshipped, or according to its voice is deaf and because of its materials it is worshipped.

The baraita is not really talking about B'S and B'H, but about disputes that are still open and have not been decided by law. In a dispute about B'S and B'H, there is really no option to choose to follow B'S.

In any case, in all three excuses, the assumption is that the Bat Kol requires the ruling of the rabbinic court, at least if one does not follow Rabbi Yehoshua, even though, simply from the issue of the BM, it appears that the halakhah has been ruled accordingly.

Comment on the contradiction of the issues

This is emphasized in the Todah 'here', in the issue there:

Here, after the voice of the voice – and if you say, "What is the hatred of the non-existent?", then it is like the voice of the voice of Rabbi Eliezer of Zehav (B"M 4:55).

How does the assumption of this issue (that the decision of the Bat Kol is valid, according to the Bible) reconcile with the issue of the BM (that the Bat Kol has no halakhic status)?

He gives two excuses:

And it must be said that it did not come out except in his honor, as the blood of the innocent.

According to this excuse, they do oversee the Bat Kol, and in the issue of BM, there is talk of a Bat Kol that was issued only in honor of the Rabbi, and was not really intended to decide a halakhic ruling (although it is not clear how the listeners there were supposed to understand this).

Second excuse:

And yet, they were against many, and the Torah said to incline after many, but here, rather, the House of Hillel was the majority, and they did not need a voice, except because of Deborah Shammai, who was a Hariphi Tefi.

What is not followed is only when it acts against the majority, since the halachic rule is that one follows the majority (this is what the Gemara says in the BM specifically, that one does not follow the halachic because it is written in the Torah "to incline after many"). If so, the halachic has no standing against the halachic, but not that it has no standing at all. And what happened here with regard to the BH? Here the halachic came out in favor of the BH, who were the majority. However, the BH has difficulty in why they even needed the halachic and did not already rule without it, as the BH already did, by virtue of the halachic "to incline after many" rule? They answer that the halachic was necessary because the BH were more pointed and harsh. I will explain this more below.

Thos ends with a difficulty:

And if you say, then why did Rabbi Yehoshua say, "There is no supervision over a female voice?" Didn't Rabbi Yehoshua say, but rather, "Avat Kol" (the father of the voice) and "Vil" (the father of the voice) that is not in the sky?" does that mean that there is no supervision at all over any female voice?

Here Tos explains that all of the above is stated according to the first excuse in the Gemara. But according to the second excuse, there are no overseers of a Bat Kol in any situation, both when it comes to deciding a halakhah and when it does not act against the rules of halakhah. However, there is a disagreement between the Tannaim (the baraita here versus Rabbi Yehoshua). It is true that it is not clear how it itself was decided (after all, it is impossible to decide according to the majority). Beyond that, I have already noted that on its face it appears that the baraita here is not a halakhah.

Conclusions

First, it is not clear why the word "Bat Kol" was even used here in the first place. Thos explains that it is because the ISAs were more severe. Does the severity stand against the majority? If not, then we have not gained anything. If so, then we are back to the situation where the word "Shabbat Kol" came to decide something against the rules of halakhah.

It seems that their intention was to say that there was a will not to follow the majority because the B's were more strict, and the Bat Kol ruled that even in such a situation one must follow the majority. In other words, she clarified for us the meaning of the halakhic rule that commands following the majority. In conclusion, she does not act against the rules of decision of the halakhic law, but only sharpens and clarifies them themselves. Thos apparently assumes that this is what a Bat Kol can do.

Did the B'S themselves accept this ruling? From many places in the Talmud it seems that they did not. In the baraita here we see that one who wants to do as the B'S says does so (although there are various excuses for this here). Likewise, in the first chapter of Bitza we find several disagreements between the B'S and the G-d regarding a meal, and there are Amoraim who ruled in favor of the B'S. The Amoraim certainly acted after the emergence of the Bat Kol, and yet they ruled as they did. How is this possible? Of course, someone who believes in the B'S will certainly not start following the G-d because of the Bat Kol, and the B'S themselves certainly did not do this. According to their view, one should follow the harshness and the majority does not rule against it.

I think the explanation for this is that the B'S Bat Kol method offers a solution that contradicts the halakha (since according to their system, it is the halakha that determines the severity, not the majority), and therefore, from their perspective, it should not be listened to, since one does not follow the Bat Kol in a place that is against the rules of halakha. The conclusion is that even after the Bat Kol, someone who believes in the B'S (both on the merits of the matter and in the law of following the majority, which determines the severity) can do the B'S. The Bat Kol came out in favor of those who do not have a position on the issue of the decision, and who do not belong to the B'S or believe like them. The Bat Kol ordered them to follow the B'S.

There is also another possibility, according to which the rule that the Lord has decreed is not a binding rule, but merely a guideline for those who do not have their own position. But for those who believe the Lord, they must certainly do as they understand and not follow the Bat Kol. I will explain this further later in the column.

Another suggestion

If we look at the situation before the issue of Bat Kol, the question arises as to why the dispute between the two houses was not resolved at all. What was special about it, compared to all the other disputes? It seems that this can be explained in the way of Tos. There was a limbo in the decision: the B"H believed that one should follow the majority of people and the B"H believed that one should follow the majority of wisdom (the severity). Therefore, the rule that one follows the majority could not resolve the halakhic disputes between the houses. But even this meta-halakhic dispute itself (whether the majority decides or the severity) cannot be resolved by voting, since each side is fortified in its meta-halakhic position (see in the column 195 On anti-paradox). B.S. will say that one should follow the severity, and in any case they will remain in their position that the severity is the determining factor, and vice versa with B.S. In such a situation, there is justification for resorting to the decision of the voice.

When there is no majority decision and no halakhic decision rule, the principle of "not in heaven" is not stated. This principle only instructs us to use the halakhic decision rules and not to seek other alternatives for them. But when we do not have a halakhic option to decide, then it is certainly possible and perhaps necessary to use a unanimous vote.

The difference between the offers

This suggestion seems very similar to Thos's second excuse, but it is not identical to it. In Thos' it is implied that the prohibition to turn to a Bat Kol is only when it is an action against the rules of halakhah (for example, when a Bat Kol instructs us to go against the majority). According to my suggestion, the prohibition to turn to a Bat Kol is only when there is a halakhic basis. When there is no halakhic basis, there is no prohibition. The indication for this difference is that the claim that the ISAs are more severe appeared in Thos only as a side note, and its purpose was to explain why it was necessary to turn to a Bat Kol. But according to my suggestion, this claim is essential to the permission itself (the permission to obey a Bat Kol stemmed from the fact that it was a limbo of the majority versus severity).

It can be said that according to Thos, there is an explanation that reconciles the ruling of God with the rule "it is not in the heavens": the rule was not stated when the action is not against the halakha. But according to my method, there is no need for an explanation. Even if this rule applies in the current situation, we cannot remain stuck because of it, and therefore we will act against it. Where a ruling is required, we will reach it even if it contradicts the relevant rule. One can of course argue that this is itself an interpretation of the rule (meaning that it does not apply where there is limbo), and this is true, but in any case it is an interpretation that we did not receive in tradition together with the rule itself, but rather arrived at it from an explanation and from lack of choice. Below we will see the meaning of this distinction.

Let me repeat this further. We have seen that according to the second excuse of Tos', the rule "it is not in heaven" is sweeping. It applies in all situations, even when there is no contradiction to the halacha. Therefore, this excuse holds that the baraita here apparently does not agree with Rabbi Yehoshua's view. Now consider what Rabbi Yehoshua himself would have done if he had been in the situation described in the Eruvin issue? Apparently, he would have been stuck forever. Note, I am not asking whether, according to Rabbi Yehoshua, it is possible to follow the halakhic rule even after the Bat Kol. Thos clearly writes that it is. I am asking a more fundamental question: What would Rabbi Yehoshua (as an observer from the side) do with the halakhic limbo if he did not supervise the Bat Kol? It seems that in his view the dispute would have remained forever unresolved since he does not supervise the Banut Kol. How fortunate that he was not there. But my argument is that he himself, if he had been present there, would have made a similar decision and obeyed the Bat Kol. This is indeed against the rule "not in the heavens" (in his view), but there is no other choice. In such a situation, it is clear to me that he would also be acting against the halakhic rule, even though in his view it applies here as well. With all due respect to the rules, there are situations in which we must deviate from them.

One of the implications of this difference is regarding the determination of a majority in a court of law. According to Thos' proposal, the Bat Kol ruled that the determining majority is the numerical majority and not the severity. Now that this has been decided, we must act this way in every context. For example, when a dispute arises in a court of law between the opinion of one scholar and the opinion of two other scholars who are less wise than him, one must follow them and not him (since numbers prevail over severity and wisdom). But according to the law, this matter is disputed by the poskim (see in the column 69, and also 79, and for example here (In Rabbi Yoel Amital's article, which deals with the majority in general, not necessarily in a court of law.) According to the poskim who believe that even today one follows the majority of wisdom and not the number, it is not clear how they interpret our issue. Ostensibly, here a directive was received that one should follow the numerical majority.

Although according to my proposal here, the conclusion is different. The fact that there was a tie between number and sharpness only allowed the sages there to resort to a voice vote, but a voice vote does not necessarily determine that the numerical majority should be followed. It is the decision that in disputes between the Sharia and the HaShem halakha, the Talmud (even the reasoning there in the Gemara does not refer to a decision on the question of the numerical majority versus sharpness). The question of number versus wisdom remains open, and each posk can decide it according to his understanding. Thus, the issue can be interpreted according to these opinions.

The role of rules

We can perhaps learn from this the proper attitude towards the rules of halakhah in general. We saw a situation in which there is a halakhic rule that leaves us stuck: "It is not in heaven." When we are in a hopeless situation, there must be a way to overcome it and reach a decision. In such a situation, we decide that this rule does not apply to such situations and deviate from it. As stated above, it is of course always possible to argue that this is itself an interpretation of the rule, but it is an interpretation that was born out of the distress and was not stated by the one who established this rule. The implication is that this is what can and should be done in other situations in which we have a problem with some halakhic rule. We saw above the example of a situation in which Rabbi Yehoshua was in a state of limbo, where I argued that he deviated from the rule.

Let's look at another context. What would happen in a situation where there is a halakhic rule that instructs us to make a certain decision, but it is clear to us that this is not the correct decision for this situation? I want to argue that even in such a situation we must act against the rule (i.e. interpret it in a way that does not apply to this case, as we did with the rule "it is not in heaven"). The rules are not insurmountable, and when a situation requires it, we must deviate from them. To clarify the matter, we will take a few examples.[2]

The first example is related to disqualifying relatives from testifying (see above). here). The Gemara and, following it, the poskim (see, for example, Rambam, Testimony of Piyush Ha-Thu, 15 and more) state that this is a decree of Scripture, meaning that there is no problem with the credibility of close witnesses, since there is a presumption that no person is a sinner and that he is not, but the Torah decreed that we should not accept their testimony for its own reasons. We do not feel that this principle is problematic, since even if two relatives come to testify about Reuven who murdered, at most we will not punish him, and if necessary we may punish him unjustly. In the law of money, it is even possible to follow the impression of the judge (see Rambam, Ref. 2 and Ref. 2D of the Sanhedrin), and therefore it is also possible to rule based on relatives.[3] Therefore, most students do not understand the great problem with this explanation (or lack of explanation) for excluding relatives. But now think about a situation in which two qualified witnesses come and convict a murderer, and then two relatives come and instigate them. Ostensibly, the testimony of relatives should not be accepted, so we will ignore the instigation and execute the murderer. Note that the conspirators are truthful, since there is only a scriptural decree not to accept their testimony as relatives. If so, we actually know that this person is not a murderer (the witnesses who convicted him are liars),[4] And yet we must kill him. Such a ruling is unthinkable, and a court in such a situation should certainly deviate from the law and exempt him from death. Is there a rule in halakha that allows this? Is there a restriction on disqualifying relatives from testifying? If there is one, please act immediately. I think the implication is that in such a situation we must deviate from the rules.

Another example belongs to the rules of jurisprudence (see above in the columns). 482 and-119). We have accepted that in disputes between Abaye and Rava, the ruling is that of Rava, with the exception of six cases marked by Yael Kagam (see Kiddushin 55:1 and parallels). However, the Rambam in several contexts rules in favor of Abaye against Rava in other disputes. For example, in the law 'Do not congregate' the Rambam (Hebrew: 87:22:14) rules in favor of Abaye that it prohibits two courts in one city. Also in the law 'I do not work, I do not have any pleasure', according to some of his commentators, the Rambam (see Nash'ei Kelim in Hebrew: Mecha P'l 57 and Hebrew: Shabbat 523:15) rules in favor of Abaye that an act done against the Torah is beneficial.

The question is how it is possible for the Rambam to go head-on against an explicit rule of jurisprudence in the Talmud. The authors of the rules have offered all kinds of reservations, some of which are incomprehensible and illogical, and also have no clear source. They qualify the rule that the Rabbis followed with all kinds of reservations in order to conform to the Rambam's rulings. The obvious question is where did the Rambam himself learn these invisible reservations? How did he allow himself not to follow explicit rules of jurisprudence in the Talmud? But according to what we have seen here, there is no need for this. If the Rambam has a reason to rule as I do in some dispute, by virtue of his own opinion or by virtue of some issue, then he will prefer it over the rule that the Rabbis followed (this is essentially a type of 'consideration').Lex SpecialisSee for example on it. hereIn the above columns, I linked this to the halakhic 'rule' that "one does not learn from generalizations even in a place where it says 'except'" (see Eruvin 27a and parallels).

We could perhaps expand and say that this means that the rules of halacha should be taken with limited certainty, since they are an approximation to halacha and not its actual definition. Just as the rules of grammar are only an approximation to correct speech (therefore, there are exceptions to every rule), they are not what define correct speech. Therefore, in the case where it is clear that the rule does not lead to the correct conclusion, it can be deviated from. We will assume that this is another one of the exceptions, even if we have a detailed list of exceptions and this case does not appear among them (as in the case of Yael Kagam).

One could perhaps expand the scope even further and argue that the rules are merely guidelines for situations in which I have no reasonable way to act based on local considerations. But if I have such a way, there is no need to resort to rules. This is a more radical view. The rule is not just an approximation, and I don't even have to freeze it in special situations of distress, but the rule is generally not stated except as a tool that helps us make decisions when we have no other way to do so.[5] There is no problem in departing from a halakhic rule when you see fit, because the rule is not intended to be sweeping and absolute. This is very similar to my suggestion above regarding the rule "it is not in the sky."

This is perhaps how we can understand the possibility of easing up in times of stress (see on this inMy articles On the meaning of voices in halacha), that is, to rely in such situations on an opinion that has not been ruled on as halacha. On the face of it, it is very difficult to justify this conduct, because if the halacha was ruled as a different opinion, then it is going against halacha because of a hardship, and we have not found such a thing (when there is no dispute, we will not go against halacha even in times of distress). But even if the halacha was not ruled on in the case before us, we still have rules for deciding on spikot (doubt from the Torah to the grave and rabbinic to the voice, etc.). If so, choosing a lenient opinion in a doubt from the Torah is going against halacha even when there is no clear ruling. How, then, is it permissible to do this in times of distress?

According to my suggestion, things are clearer here. If I am in a time of stress, then this itself allows me, halakhically, to choose a mitigating opinion, meaning that I have a way to decide the question before me. Now I am no longer in doubt, and in any case the rule that requires me to go to the extreme with sufficient certainty does not apply to me. This can of course be said only if I assume that the rule that one must go to the extreme with sufficient certainty is stated in the Torah as a rule that helps a situation where I have no other way to decide. But when I have another way to decide, this rule is not stated there at all. If we assume that the time of stress is itself a legitimate way to decide in halakhic terms, then in any case there is no need to consider the rule that commands me to go to the extreme when there is no decision. In other words, the rule of doubt from the Torah to the extreme is a rule that is invoked last, only when all else fails.

This is what I suggested above regarding "not in the heavens." It may also apply to the situation that prevailed between the B.H. and the B.S., but in a state of limbo there is no choice but to act against the rule. My suggestion here is that this is the case with all halakhic rules. There are situations in which we must deviate from them, and this does not necessarily have to be viewed as a special permission or deviation from the halakhah. This is the halakhah itself. The rules are not the halakhah itself, but at most an approximation to it, or a default guideline when there is no other option. This of course requires more comprehensive consideration and research, on different types of rules and types of situations, and I have come here only to point out the principle direction.

[1] See also the prologue to the third book of the trilogy.

[2] I will not bring up the law of "offense for its own sake" here, as it is reasonable to say that this is an action that is not in accordance with halachah. I am looking for halachic examples.

[3] This is my opinion. Most of the latter did not think so. See on this inMigo brochure my.

[4] Although the intention is also the decree of the scripture, I showed in my article The above That cannot be interpreted literally. It is clear that the second sect is truly more loyal than the first.

[5] See the response. here A discussion on the essence of the rules of jurisprudence in Halacha.

23 תגובות

  1. Adds: Why did the House of Hillel rule against the House of Shammai of the Tefi sect?
    Because Beit Hillel is more respectful, they also consider the opinion that disagrees with them and then decide according to the truth and not just their own perception.

  2. This is consistent with the rule that Beit Yosef rules according to the majority between Maimonides, the Rif, and the Rosh, or the rule that Rabbi Ovadia rules according to the Shulchan Aruch.

    Just a note, you say about conspiring witnesses that they speak the truth, only that there is a written decree, that is not accurate, because everything that conspiring witnesses accept is puzzling in itself (meaning that their testimony is accepted completely and the first sect is punished and their testimony is not used as a doubt and no one is punished) and it can be considered a written decree, and therefore it can be regarded as a written decree that cancels the written decree.
    They are still no less than witnesses to the denial, so your words can still stand, even though there is one sect here that is probably lying anyway.

    1. Do you mean that it fits with their exceptions to the rule they themselves set?
      I alluded to your question about conspiring witnesses in a reference in note 4 to my article on the subject. There I dealt with it in detail.

      1. Indeed, what I meant was that rules exist primarily to be broken.

        Regarding conspiring witnesses, I didn't notice the comment. I accept that there is an explanation, leaning towards the interpretation you gave to Maimonides.

        A question that has been nagging me for a long time is to what extent they were discussed technically, that is, if according to the Halacha on paper, one is supposed to be executed but the judge has doubts, what do we do?
        Of course, there is the matter of Rabbi Tarfon and Rabbi Akiva who say that no one would ever have been killed (which, incidentally, appears in Tractate Makot), but even on this the Gemara says that they get hung up on technical details.
        It is also interesting that on this issue, the criticism is that they are often bloodthirsty, meaning that for offenses that are seemingly between a person and a place, there is no criticism of the system (leaving a lot of room for demanding and receiving a reward).
        But what really concerns me is whether all the technical details have been settled and the judges still have doubts about the veracity of the testimony, for example. I don't know of any sources that deal with this, if any.

        1. First, there is the law of "deception," meaning that if a judge feels that despite having evidence, this is not the truth, he can withdraw from the case. I was of course talking about something else. In my case, this is a situation where the law is clear and the reality is clear, but the result is problematic.
          Regarding the criticism of the RA and RA, I don't think the intention is specifically to shed blood. They are many criminals in Israel, and not necessarily murderers. I wrote here in the past about this issue, and I explained that the RA was the president of the Sanhedrin and had practical responsibility, and the RA and RA who were not in the Sanhedrin were scholars without practical responsibility. This is probably the root of the argument.

  3. 1- Regarding the actual interpretation of the words of the Rabbi, "It is not in the heavens," I did not understand that his intention was to learn this from the verse, but rather that the basis of the rule is from the explanation [just as they did not accept evidence from the carob tree and the water well without a verse] and from the fulfillment of this interpretation in the verse (the NAFKM is that the verse does not only contain what the explanation gives and nothing more)
    2-According to your explanation in Tos, it is puzzling what benefit there is in Bat Kol, that is, to what extent is Bat Kol not useful for the Shavsha? If so, there is no benefit in its appearance even for the person who is satisfied (who is not from these ba'ti midrash), since the reference to it itself depends on the position it is intended to clarify.
    3- I understood that even according to Thos, there was no party whose advantage in sharpness in principle negated the rule of following the majority. It is also simple to say that in any case there is a wisdom advantage for one of the parties, we would not say majority rule, because then we would never follow the majority, because who knows how to say that those who argue are exactly equal in their wisdom (and if the majority is superior in wisdom, then God forbid we would be ruled like them and we would not need majority rule only in equals).
    The entire debate between B.S. and B.H. revolves around the principle that the majority is only the law of conduct. And like all other rules of jurisprudence and halacha, it cannot say what the truth is in the debate before us, only how we should make decisions and act on the disputed matter. [For the sake of the matter, even witnesses do not truly ascertain the reality and it is only the law of conduct to say that they ascertain, as the Maimonides says in Yesudas: "Just as we were commanded to decide the case according to two qualified witnesses, and even though it is possible that they testified falsely, since they are qualified, we uphold them on their validity. And in these matters and the like, we say that things are hidden to the Lord our God and things are revealed to us and to our children, and we say that man sees with the eyes, but the Lord sees with the heart"].
    Another principle is that there is a fundamental advantage for someone who knows the truth about themselves, so that even against a majority, they must act according to their own opinion (like someone who knows about a piece of milk, even if a hundred witnesses say it is fat, they will not listen to them). I will use your terminology, a first-order decision is always preferable to a second-order decision. As the Maimonides says in the Laws of the Meritorious, in the Disputation, in the Explanation, and in the Interpretation, they do not need to be great in wisdom in the Minyan.
    So far, as I understand it, things are consistent with the suggestion you made ("that you don't always have to follow the rules." Only, in my opinion, there is no exception to the rule here at all, since it was not stated in a way that is known how to act, but only in the place provided). But in my opinion, there is a level of 'second-order' knowledge that is equal to 'first-order' knowledge. For example, a reasonable person would respond with disdain to conspiracy claims regarding the moon landing, as you responded in a previous response. And the disdain is not just "leave me alone, you failed to arouse my curiosity," but "you failed to arouse my doubt." Such knowledge is not just a "rule of conduct," but is an accepted way of taking a position on a particular subject. And even if I have not researched the subject, I will consider the opinion that was given as a position that I accept as truth and as knowledge about reality (and as an analytical rather than synthetic position).
    Example - On the question of why there is an obligation to accept and not disagree with the Talmud, the opinion of the Chazo"a is "because they were truly wise, and what are you worth compared to them..." In my analytical opinion, it is impossible to say that there is some kind of reasoning here that we are obligated to listen to their words even where we believe they were wrong, except that the Chazo"a himself assumes that anyone who recognizes their greatness will never approve a position against their words (a point that can certainly be disputed). So here there is not just a formal consideration (as in the opinion of the Gra Wasserman) to obey their words, but a substantive consideration.
    Also regarding the dispute between B"S and B"H - B"S held themselves to be the sharpest of the points to such an extent that B"S's words instead of their own words do not matter. B"S did not accept their position (a fact that they did not hesitate to disagree with them). Hence the question of how the average person would act? How would he decide this question? After all, there are no analytical tools to prove whether B"S is not truly far superior to B"S, and in this sense there is a synthetic position here. Bat Kol would be useful for this. After all, everything that we do not listen to Bat Kol according to my words is not because the Torah commanded not to listen to her, but because there is a second-order consideration here that cannot override a first-order consideration (the analytical is superior to the synthetic, reason is superior to faith, etc.). But instead of a first-order decision, we will accept a second-order decision.
    According to this, it is also explained by Thos that the appearance of the Bat Kol will benefit the common man even according to their system, and that the MM will not benefit them for themselves, and yet they hold their opinion against the BH (since in every dispute there is a first-order consideration that is superior to the Bat Kol consideration, which is a second-order consideration). And it is also explained that the words of Thos Shas did not accept that one should follow the majority just because they are more precise.

    1. 1. I understood it that way too. That's why I wrote this column, to show that it's not so.
      2. Not true. I distinguished between two levels of discussion. A person can have an opinion on the halakhic issue in question, but on the question of which majority is the determining one, he has no position. After all, even without all my words, you can see for yourself that the halakhic were really not convinced and the Amoraim ruled as they did. So how do you explain this? It has nothing to do with my picture specifically.
      3. We follow the majority of people except where wisdom has a clear advantage over foolishness. Therefore, the rule of following the majority has significance. And indeed, there are several poskim who wrote in the Book of Torah that what determines is the majority of wisdom, and they were not bothered by the fact that it would lead to a situation where we would not be able to decide. Because that would not really lead to that, and so on.
      Both the witnesses and the majority certainly clarify the reality. The sources you cited do not contain a shred of evidence against this. However, this clarification should receive a seal of approval that it is sufficient. Two witnesses definitely clarify the reality and are not just a guideline. But there was a place to say that five witnesses would be needed or that one would be enough, and therefore the Torah states that two are needed and two are enough.
      I didn't understand the long-windedness regarding the connection between analyticity and syntheticity.

      1. 2- What I tried to say (more at length in Part 3, which I wrote) is that in my opinion the Amoraim did not rule against the Bat Kol, but rather ruled on the litigants themselves. That is, because the Bat Kol is a ruling for lack of knowledge, just as the majority ruling is for lack of knowledge, and the entire majority ruling belongs where there is doubt, meaning that a person does not have a position on the matter before him. But where he has a position on the matter itself, then he does not have the right to follow the majority (and as the Rabbis ruled in the disputes in the interpretation, not because they are great in wisdom or in number).

        (3-) If we follow this path, then even the B'S admit that a person "who has not studied the issue" and does not have a position on the matter, must follow the Bat Kol. And the Amoraim who followed the B'S method were because they believed the same as them on the matter itself, and it is not appropriate to decide by a Bat Kol, which is a second-order decision, in a place where a person has a clear position on the matter before him [in which case he has a first-order decision].

        I added another level to this, that the ISA themselves may have disagreed with the ISA to begin with and did not believe that another person is obligated to listen to the ISA even though the majority is with them, since in their opinion they are much more pointed than the ISA, - for this reason the ISA's words do not replace their words. Here I added that this argument for the ISA's method is not just a consideration to 'act' like them - but that a reasonable person can assume that they are right in their claim without having to refer to the body of the issue (as in the case of the moon landing). And since it is necessary for the ordinary person, there is a first-order consideration to assume that the ISA is right and there is no room for second-order considerations that are intended for the person who is satisfied.

        Here was a subtle point that I was unable to write down successfully at first, - according to the last argument (-whose severity is so great that one can rely on it "and know" according to it, and therefore there is no place for the laws of "leadership"), again there is no use in a voice. After all, according to their method, in every dispute, every person has a perception [at the level of knowledge] that the truth is the same. So why did it come out at all?

        But it really seems that the average person on the street still has to hear a woman's voice [and therefore she came out], even according to the Bible.
        After all, the reason why the B'S claimed that one should follow their words against the Rabbi is based first and foremost on the assumption that they are much more severe than the Rabbis. But the Rabbis thought that they certainly deserved to be part of the B'S group and that the differences did not justify overriding their opinion because of the B'S opinion. Thus, the question that should be discussed is what is the true level of severity of the B'S compared to the Rabbis (and accordingly - should we follow the severe ones or the majority).
        Such an argument is an argument that could not be analytically clarified through research, and the reason is simple - to the extent that a person claims to be much smarter than me and therefore I cannot understand him, I have no way of denying him. Only, in the average case, I will simply understand that I have no reason to assume that he is really saying things that I do not understand due to my shortsightedness, but that he is talking nonsense (a person is instinctively enslaved to his own mental autonomy). But in the case where I heard a physics professor talking about quantum theory, although the things sound somewhere between strange and delusional, I assume from the beginning - even before I heard proof/explanation - that it is delusional to me but at most strange but real and even genius to someone who deals with the field. Just like a small child is loaded with very important insights about life... but still understands that there is a chance that his father knows something about this life that he does not yet know (and I added that I understood this to be the perception of the Chazo"a in relation to the Sages, and that is why there is no dispute about the Talmud).
        The same is true of B.S. compared to B.H., since B.S. are more pointed (in everyone's opinion), it is not possible to analytically prove that they are wrong in the very claim that they are so pointed that B.S.'s opinion is not worthy of consideration. Nor is it possible to prove that B.S. are wrong, since factually they fight back with a hair and are not friars themselves. But on the other hand, perhaps if we were as sharp as B.S. we would understand that B.S. simply does not understand the depths of B.S.'s words.
        Thus, the position of the ordinary observer-person in relation to the harshness of the B.S. is a synthetic position. In the sense that this position is the starting point of the discourse and the A.S. seeks to clarify the same claim from within the discourse. (And of course the B.S. themselves relied on their mental anatomy, and so did the B.S. But the observer is embarrassed and does not have the tools to prefer one claim over another.)

        In such a place, we have no further clarification from within the discourse, and we must turn to an external means that will clarify whether it is appropriate for God to disagree with the Bible. And indeed, the voice of the voice came out and said that it is appropriate [and the halakha is fulfilled according to their words, Dasli' Bat Ruba].
        And even the B.S. understand that they themselves are subject to their own opinion and that reason is obligatory, but the person on the street does not have such subjection (he does not know the issue at all and he also does not "know" what is clear about them, that they are a level plus above the B.S.) and he has to follow the voice of the voice.

        4* I don't want to divert the discussion, but it is clear as day in the language of the Rambam that I cited that witnesses are not really a clarification, only the Torah said to act as if the matter were clarified. "And it is possible that he will perform a sign and a miracle and is not a prophet, and this sign has things in his body, and yet it is commanded to hear him, since a man is great and wise and worthy of prophecy [he] is placed on the basis of his authority, which we have been commanded to do. Just as we were commanded to decide the case based on two qualified witnesses, and although it is possible that they testified falsely, since they are qualified with us, we place them on their validity. And in these and similar matters it is said that things are hidden to the Lord our God and things are revealed to us and to our children, and it is said that man sees with the eyes, and the Lord sees with the heart." - Yesodat, end of chapter 7. [Truly, you don't need the Rambam to understand that hearing is not similar to seeing. And here there is only a threshold of probability, but certainly not at the level of knowledge].

        I didn't want to comment from the beginning, but the direct implication of this being just a rule of conduct is that instead of two conspiring witnesses who are relatives coming, we will not discuss that there is a "deceit of deception" here. It is certainly true that it is more likely to believe the conspiring witnesses than the instigating witnesses, but the legality of the testimony of the conspirators is equal to other testimonies in the matter, so there is no real investigation of reality from the very testimony of their witnesses, only if the Torah gives validity to conducting an investigation here based on their testimony. And the Torah did not give this validity to the relatives, so there is a "probability" here - that justice is with the instigators, against a lower probability - that the truth is with the instigators, but the Torah considered precisely the instigators before us as investigators. And so this is not a question of probability versus low probability, but probability versus investigation.

        1. 2-3. So you go back to my formulation. The rule is valid but not binding in itself, so when I have a different position there is no need to follow it. It has nothing to do with the question of whether a majority is leadership or clarification. If that is what you call leadership, then it is just a change of name. I don't see what the argument is about.
          The question of how one decides who is more severe than whom is, of course, a good question, but the fact that the Gemara and the Toss did determine that the Shab-e-Sh is more severe than Tefi is a good question. That is, there is a way to determine this. When we don't know, then we revert to the usual majority rule for all opinions.
          4. Regarding Maimonides, you are of course wrong, and I have already explained this. You are confusing the claim that the testimony of two witnesses is not certain with the claim that this is an arbitrary leadership.
          Regarding conspiring witnesses, see my article that I referenced.

          1. * For my move, the rules weren't broken, they weren't stated in a place like this.
            * The main point of the length is to explain that even the Toss did not intend to say that a general question was decided here, but rather a private question in relation to reality.
            * It is clear that a person has ways of seeing who is sharper than his fellow man. But only in a comparative manner, one against the other. What cannot be defined is the gap between them, whether it is such that it justifies not attributing importance to the opinions of those who disagree (this is a question of quality, I think it can be likened to what you brought from the book with the Zen and the motorcycle, which cannot be defined but can certainly be seen to be seen).
            *Regarding witnesses, I agree that it is more likely to assume that the truth is with them, but they certainly do not raise the perception of reality to the level of knowledge. It does not come close to a level of certainty like the certainty that the Twin Towers fell. That the Americans landed on the moon, etc.
            The Rambam compares them to accepting the words of a prophet, who writes that even magicians can do some trick to predict the future, and in any case we must accept his words, so too in the witnesses. His language, "We were commanded to cut off the judgment," "the hidden things of God," also shows what "certainty" the Rambam attributes to the witnesses.

            Meanwhile, I think it's possible that everything about witnesses is also about a synthetic position...🤦‍♂️😉

            1. I didn't understand all the long story, it's just clear to me that witnesses are not a state of certain knowledge.

  4. A1. You have established the words of the Sages that the verses also deal with the attainment of the Torah and not only with its fulfillment. But why was it not said that although the decision is left to humans, where there is a revelation from heaven then the revelation prevails (not only when there is limbo. In the oven of the Achanai, the revelation as Rabbi Eliezer will prevail over the decision of humans). It is not only in heaven, but it is certainly also in heaven.
    A2. It simply seems that the Sages do not have the authority to determine that it is not in heaven. If I hear a faithful revelation from heaven and the Sages tell me to ignore the revelation, then I will certainly ignore the Sages. The words of the rabbi and the words of the student are the words of those who hear. At most, the Sages can say that where there is no revelation, one can rely on a wise man and on reason, and not everything is just according to the laws of doubt.
    Even if the Torah were explicit that there are no overseers of a Bat Kol and that no prophet is permitted to innovate anything, it is still not at all clear that we will not oversee a reliable Bat Kol (because in what way is it less good than the Torah itself if not in terms of reliability). And now that this is just an interpretation, then surely the Bat Kol itself believes in a different interpretation of the Torah and why shouldn't we go with it (by the way, there is also a lex specialis in its favor).
    A3. (The melody repeats again). If it is not in heaven, then what is the meaning of halakhic monism, that is, what defines the objective halakhic truth that you hold (and in addition, there is also some side law given monism called autonomy). If something is not the Torah of God, which is objective truth and is found in heaven, then what is the point of studying it, except for the need for technical knowledge to know what to do.

    B. You wrote that Beit Hillel and Beit Shammai had a problem (limbo) and therefore bypassed the rule (it is not in the sky). Why is such a lack of decision problematic? According to this, if a Bat Kol were to come out today to decide between the Shach and the Pharisee, what law would we then follow this Bat Kol? Or maybe only in public matters such as conversion? In your opinion, should someone who believes that the Ari received revelations from God decide as the Ari does when there is a dispute over revelation?

    C. In the Rambam who ruled that my father was against the rule, you say that it is not a question because perhaps he has a side explanation or revelation. If there is such an explanation, it should be 'immediately revealed.' This explanation should be of such force that we think it is reasonable to assume that in all the other disputes (in which the Rambam adhered to the rules of the ruling as a reward for my mother) the Rambam did not happen to have an explanation of a similar force that was contrary to the rule. In other words, in any case, we need to find uniqueness here for these isolated cases, and distancing the uniqueness from the "explanation" does not help because we really need to find an explanation of a unique force in these isolated cases *and only in them*. The Amoraim could certainly bypass from their explanation a direct ruling rule that Amoraim like them had conquered, and even did so (as is made clear, for example, in the long discussion of the Gemara in Eruvin Mo regarding the validity of the personal rules of ruling).

    1. A1. I didn't understand. When there is a revelation, is it necessary/permissible to obey it? So when is it forbidden? What is the innovation that is not in heaven? When heaven says nothing?
      A2. The Sages did not establish this, but rather learned it from the Torah. This is precisely what I tried to show.
      A3. There is one halachic truth and this is the intention of God. Each of us must try to reach it, and only one of the dissenters succeeds in doing so. Nevertheless, there is an obligation to rule autonomously, and it outweighs the value of the truth.
      B. I explained this in the prologue to the third book. There was a fear of losing the people and the Torah in general. There was, for the first time, a division of the public into two parts, two groups, each holding a completely different mishnah that do not speak to each other. Two blocs. It is not like disputes over one or another halakhic issue. Especially if these are issues that do need to be decided for the benefit of the public. What's more, it happened in a framework that did not yet recognize the phenomenon of dispute in its full scope and did not know how to deal with it.
      C. This does not have to be an explanation. It may also be due to a parallel issue. In any case, this is, in my opinion, the most likely explanation for Maimonides' exceptions.

      1. A1. The innovation is that human decision-making can be trusted according to assumptions and that it is within the human power to understand. Otherwise, we would have to resort to the laws of doubt in everything indefinitely.
        A2. The Sages went to the extreme that even when we find someone who ascends to heaven for us and takes it from us and makes it heard, we should not treat him. The Torah should be interpreted in the above-mentioned scholastic sense that where we do not find such a person, we can still get along. This idea that it is not in heaven is so absurd and far-fetched to me that I find it hard to believe that anyone really thinks that way.

  5. A. In the second excuse in the Gemara, you explained a dispute between Rabbi Yehoshua and the Baraita about whether to observe the Bat Kol (Rabbi Yehoshua does not), that is, whether there is a rule that is not in the parable (Rabbi Yehoshua does) and you wrote that this is a dispute about whether the halakha has an obligation to rule according to Beit Hillel (Rabbi Yehoshua does not have an obligation) and you stood in bewilderment, because on the one hand the halakha is according to Rabbi Yehoshua and on the other hand there is an obligation to rule according to Beit Hillel.
    Apparently the interpretation in the Gemara is that the entire baraita is Rabbi Yehoshua and after Bat Kol, and then Rabbi Yehoshua says the halakha according to Beit Hillel (because that is his opinion), but in any case, whoever wants to do it according to Beit Shammai does so. Just as Rabbi Yehoshua said before Bat Kol came. And so the language of the Gemara is a bit distorted, in that in the first excuse it made separate occurrences "here ... and here," while in the second excuse the wording is different (I checked several other occurrences of "I've been afraid of my mother" in the Gemara, and the wording here and here is used).

    B. Completely biased. The Tosafots say at the beginning (on the first excuse in the Gemara) that the Shabbat Kol according to Rabbi Eliezer is weaker than the Bat Kol according to Beit Hillel. Then they have difficulty in how the Gemara (in the second excuse) is based on Rabbi Yehoshua not observing the weak Bat Kol according to Rabbi Eliezer in order to claim that Rabbi Yehoshua does not observe the strong Bat Kol according to Beit Hillel (the Tanna proposal requires substantiation, not possibility). And the Tosafots respond that although Rabbi Yehoshua ruled out a weak Bat Kol, his reasoning and wording rule out every Bat Kol in the world, and therefore the Gemara (in all excuses) holds the view that Rabbi Yehoshua does not observe the Bat Kol at all. Is this how you understand the Tosafots? Or another interpretation (some wording made me wonder if you have a different interpretation).

    C. I found (but did not look into it) that in the Yad Yivamot the opinion that "they did the house of Shammai according to their words" even after Bat Kol is like Rabbi Yehoshua who did not consider Bat Kol at all.

    1. A. It may be possible, but it really doesn't seem simple to me. Certainly not in the West.
      B. That's how I understood it too.
      C. There is a parallel issue there and this is indeed one of the possibilities there as well.

  6. Rabbi Zeini reached a similar conclusion, that the rules are the last resort only if there is no other way to decide.

  7. In the book of the "Sad" of the "Eshak" and "Vailach" of the "Pg"

    To the best of my recollection, the ruling as a single person in times of need is specifically in matters of rabbinic law and not in the Dauraita (which is sufficient for the matter).

    Best regards, Ya'far

  8. Absolutely not. After all, if it is a rabbinical doubt, then there is no need for a time of urgency. And perhaps you mean that there is an individual versus many and in principle the law is as the majority, but in rabbinical matters one can follow the opinion of the individual. But if that is what you meant, then why is it that rabbinical doubt is a matter of opinion? After all, this is not a situation of doubt.
    Once again, I saw that Rabbi Shilat brought up a controversy here: https://www.yeshiva.org.il/midrash/24918
    And in my opinion, it is a Pishta that one goes to the Kola even in Torah, at least in times of great distress. Thus the Rema says in the commentary on the book of the Rishba:

    And if it is a prohibition and an exception, and it is a matter of prohibition from the Torah – he will go to the extreme, and if it is not a matter of the rabbis – he will go after the easy one, and precisely if the two parties are equal, but they do not rely on the words of a lesser one against the words of a greater one in wisdom and in number, even in times of need, then there would also be a great loss, and likewise if it was an individual against many, they follow the many everywhere.

    A rabbi who did not divide between rabbis and Dauriat.
    Indeed, the Rema, in the introduction to the Torah of Hatat, writes that he never leniently dealt with something that was forbidden by law. See my articles 'On Kula and Gumra'.

  9. 1. I assume you don't accept this as a historical truth that has been proven to be true. How do you understand this? Is it just the creation of a myth in retrospect to decide a dispute that has no other way of deciding? Did they lie?

    2. Why do we even need rules of jurisprudence that rule as X and not Y, instead of discussing the substance of the claims on each issue?

    1. 1. Indeed, I do not think this is a factual description. As Rabbi Margaliot wrote in the introduction to his edition of the Responsorial Psalm from Heaven regarding the words of the Rabbi "The Holy Spirit appeared in our synagogue."
      There was a feeling (intuition) that a decision had to be made, and perhaps it even said how it should be made. The mythical description is nothing more than a legend or myth that accompanies this decision. A myth is not a lie but a genre for conveying messages. Did the Rav lie? Absolutely not. Especially since even in the Babylonian and Jerusalemite versions we find "Hechi Demi Bat Kol," and the answers are exactly of this type and not anything involving Bat Kols coming out of the sky. Coincidences and listening to the environment.
      2. The way the Tosheba, Mishnah, and Gemara should be written. The feeling was that there was no escape and that a framework for discussions should be established. Furthermore, I have written more than once that in my opinion the rules do not replace substantive discussion. They only teach us what to do when we do not have a substantive conclusion. Therefore, Maimonides ruled as I did in additional places to Ya'al Kagam, and the Gemara says that we do not learn from the rules even in a place where it says except. Of course, the rule itself is based on poetry, which is closer to the truth. That is, the halakha is like a Moel in law against a Rav and like a Rav against Shmuel in prohibitions because their expertise was such. This does not mean that it will always lead to the truth, but if a rule needs to be established, then it makes sense to establish it this way.

      1. 1. So, your entire discussion here about "not in heaven" needs re-explanation. It's a legitimate intuition like all the other intuitions we use in discussions.

Leave a Reply

קרא גם את הטור הזה
Close
Back to top button