New on the site: Michi-bot. An intelligent assistant based on the writings of Rabbi Michael Avraham.

Modal Logic and Ontological Arguments (Column 580)

With God’s help

Disclaimer: This post was translated from Hebrew using AI (ChatGPT 5 Thinking), so there may be inaccuracies or nuances lost. If something seems unclear, please refer to the Hebrew original or contact us for clarification.

A few months ago Ariel posted on an American analytic Christian website, bringing a formulation of the well‑known philosophers Alvin Plantinga’s ontological argument (see e.g. here and here; I mentioned it briefly in Column 561 and a bit more in Column 301). This is a good opportunity to get to know modal logic, and that’s what we’ll do. We’ll start with a quick primer in logic (this will require some acquaintance with the formalism) and then move on to ontological arguments in general; in particular, we’ll return to Plantinga’s argument and examine how people attack it.

Modal Logic: Basic Notation and Relations

Modal logic deals with the notions of possibility and necessity. The starting point is that there’s a difference between saying that a proposition P is (now) true and saying that it is necessarily true. For example, the statement that the sun is currently shining is true, but not necessary; the state of affairs could have been otherwise. A truth of that sort is called a contingent truth. By contrast, the disjunction “either the sun is shining or it isn’t” is a necessary truth; there cannot be a different situation in which that does not hold. Likewise, the statement that massive bodies are attracted to the earth (gravity) is, for us, always true, but it could have been otherwise in some other world (loosely speaking). There’s also a difference between a proposition that is impossible (e.g., if it contains a logical contradiction) and one that is merely false in fact. In between, we have what is possible.

Two basic modal operators are customary:

(1) \Box P — “necessarily P”;    \Diamond P — “possibly P”.

These operators are interconnected. For example, to say that P is not necessary is the same as saying it is possibly not (equivalently: “it’s not the case that necessarily P” = “possibly not‑P”):

(2) \Diamond P = \neg\,\Box\,\neg P and \neg\,\Diamond P = \Box\,\neg P.

Another useful connection (in the strong S5 system that’s often assumed in these discussions) is:

(3) \Diamond P \to \Box \Diamond P    (“If P is possible, then it is necessarily possible”).

Note also the distinction between “it is necessary that (if P then Q)” and “if P then (necessarily Q)”. These are not the same claim:

(4) \Box(P \to Q) \not\equiv (P \to \Box Q).

This very distinction underlies Judith Ronen’s proposed solution to the problem of foreknowledge and free choice (see Column 301) and my critique there.

Possible‑Worlds Semantics

A common interpretation of the modal operators is in terms of possible worlds. We assume there are countless conceivable “worlds,” each with a (perhaps) different reality. Any scenario we can coherently imagine is, in principle, a possible world. Of those worlds, one is actual (ours), but the others are worlds that could have been actual. Within this framework, to say that a proposition P is necessary means: P is true in all possible worlds. To say that it is impossible means: it is true in none of them. And to say it is possible means: there is at least one possible world in which it holds (one can also talk about degrees of plausibility by counting in how many worlds it holds, though we won’t need that here).

This semantics allows us to translate reasoning about necessity and possibility into ordinary reasoning about truth and falsity across worlds. Many of the useful logical connections we saw above follow immediately from this picture.

Quantifiers and the Analogy (and Its Limits)

At first glance the relation between modal operators and the quantifiers of predicate logic is very close. In predicate logic we talk about a subject x having property P: written as P(x). The quantifiers are: “for all x” (∀x) and “there exists an x” (∃x). There are well‑known relations between them (Boethius’s “square of opposition,” echoed by Maimonides). For example, the negation of “for all x, P(x)” is “there exists an x such that not‑P(x),” and the negation of “there exists an x such that P(x)” is “for all x, not‑P(x).” These mirror exactly the relations (2) above between ◊ and □.

This is unsurprising under possible‑worlds semantics: saying that a proposition is necessary is like saying it is true for all worlds; saying that it is possible is like saying it is true in some world. Yet the analogy is not perfect. There is a classic debate (already in Aristotle, with challenge from George Boole) about whether an existential claim follows from a universal one. For instance, “all aliens have wings” does not entail “there are (winged) aliens” if, in fact, there are no aliens. Boole spoke of vacuous truths of the form “if there were aliens, they would have wings.” In possible‑worlds semantics, by contrast, quantification is over the space of worlds (including merely imaginary ones), so the vacuum issue doesn’t arise in the same way; the quantifiers range over the class of worlds, not over objects that may or may not exist in ours. The upshot: the similarity is instructive but incomplete; one cannot naively translate modal logic into plain predicate logic merely by replacing □ with ∀ and ◊ with ∃.

Ontological Arguments: A General Glance

Kant coined the label “ontological argument” for proofs that derive a claim about what exists from mere definitions and conceptual analysis, without empirical premises. Anselm proposed such an argument for the existence of God (I discuss him extensively in my first notebook and in my book The First Meditation), and Descartes offered an ontological argument for our own existence (see Column 363). It is widely held—largely following Kant—that such arguments cannot succeed: definitions are arbitrary and, by themselves, cannot yield facts about the world. To evaluate an ontological argument, you must either locate a hidden premise or show an invalid step. I tend to the camp that says there are no successful ontological arguments: in every case, either a premise has been smuggled in, or the argument is invalid. Sometimes it takes work to expose this.

Plantinga’s Modal Ontological Argument

(See the sources linked above and in my Q&A: The Modal Ontological Proof.) Plantinga presents a proof of God’s existence via modal logic, as an upgrade to Anselm’s. Roughly:

  1. Definition: God is the perfect being whose existence is necessary.
  2. Premise: It is possible that God exists (i.e., the divine concept is coherent; not self‑contradictory).
  3. From (2): There is a possible world in which God exists.
  4. From (1): If God exists in any world, He exists in all worlds (that’s what it means to exist necessarily). Hence, He exists in our world.
  5. Conclusion: God exists—and, indeed, His existence is necessary.

The definition in (1) is a definition; as long as it harbors no contradiction there is no bar to defining a concept that way (definitions alone aren’t claims about the world). The interesting step is (2). Atheists typically don’t claim that the very concept of God is contradictory; the argument thus seems to corner them: either embrace contradiction, or accept the conclusion. That would be a significant philosophical achievement for Plantinga (and shifts, to an extent, the burden of proof). Yet, in my view, this argument fails—not because it smuggles a premise but because it is invalid in an important way. Let’s see how.

Counterexample as Methodological Clue

You can produce parallel “proofs” for all sorts of things: a necessary fairy with wings, a perfect island, or even a necessarily salty sugar. For example: perhaps there is a world containing necessarily sour sugar; but if in that world sourness is essential to sugar, then in every world there must be sour sugar. QED. Familiar attacks on Anselm (like Gaunilo’s “perfect island”) go in this spirit. Such counterexamples do not, by themselves, refute an argument; they warn that something is amiss. To truly refute an ontological argument one must locate the precise flaw in the reasoning.

The Real Flaw: Two Senses of “Necessity”

Logic—modal logic included—talks about the truth status of propositions, not about facts themselves. Plantinga’s argument, at best, shows that the proposition “God exists” holds necessarily (i.e., in every world). But when we ordinarily say that God is necessary existence or a necessary being, we mean something metaphysical: that God’s mode of being is such that He cannot fail to exist—His existence is intrinsically necessary. That is a claim about reality, not about our sentences. Mixing these is the same confusion that underlies the problem of “logical determinism”: conflating the necessity of our knowledge/statement about the future with the necessity of the future itself.

I have elsewhere distinguished between the claim “it is necessary that (P → Q)” and “P necessarily brings about Q.” The first is a logical claim about propositions across worlds; the second is a metaphysical claim about the way the world is. One can symbolize the difference by introducing a special “necessary entailment” arrow to distinguish it from ordinary entailment. The metaphysical necessity of God’s existence—if true—speaks about the world, not merely about sentences that are true in all possible worlds.

Returning to Plantinga: his definition treats God’s necessary existence as a metaphysical necessity (an intrinsic feature of the being). But the reasoning proceeds in the logical register of modal truth across worlds. The crucial move—“there is a world in which a necessarily existing being exists; therefore the being exists in all worlds”—slides from one register to the other. If we keep the semantics straight, the premise already smuggles in the conclusion: to assert “in some world there exists a being whose existence is necessary (in our metaphysical sense)” is simply to assert that there exists a being that exists in all worlds. That is question‑begging.

Put differently: the argument doesn’t prove that God exists; it proves—by reductio—that the premise “the divine concept is coherent and allows for a possibly necessary being” is not an innocuous, modest premise. It embeds the conclusion. That’s why the same pattern lets you “prove” perfect islands and salty sugar. The modal language hides the leap.

Further Reading

(For additional background see also: here, here and here.)

This translation preserves the original structure and style and updates all direct links to mikyab.net so that they include /en immediately after .net.


Discover more from הרב מיכאל אברהם

Subscribe to get the latest posts sent to your email.

17 תגובות

  1. Hi
    Thanks for an insightful column.
    I think your criticism of Plantinga is wrong, but I admit that I'm not sure I understood it correctly.
    First, I'll formulate the gist of your argument in my own words. If you think I did her justice, you can move on and address the conclusion I draw from it (that Plantinga's argument works).

    You claim that Plantinga mixes up logical and metaphysical arguments: the first is strict and necessary but at the same time also devoid of descriptive content (it makes no factual claims about the world), the second describes possible facts but their ontological status is not strict and necessary. Was I accurate in describing your position?
    I suggest that Plantinga does not “mix up” but rather distinguishes between ontological and logical arguments, but that he insists on a relationship of dependence or derivation between the two. Therefore, he would answer you that, regarding the concept of the necessary being (God), it is impossible to ignore that dependence as you are trying to do. Such an ignoring misses the power of the entire process.

    1. I'm not sure I understood you, but I don't think that's what I wrote. I was talking about claims, not arguments. The claim "God exists necessarily" is a metaphysical claim, and the claim "the claim "God exists" is necessarily true" is a different logical claim from the previous one. The metaphysical claim cannot be applied to possible worlds. Modal logic deals with logical, not metaphysical, claims.

      1. You claimed that Plantinga “mixes” between the two types of claims. Try to think about it differently (as I suggested to you): he does not mix but claims that there is a dependence between the two types. I think the problem with your view is that you assume that logic is always formal and empty and therefore logical claims never concern content (facts). Plantinga tells you: you are mostly right but there is one anomaly that you must examine. This is the anomaly of the absolutely necessary concept of being. There, for logic to work, you must assume a “meta-logical”reality.

        I don't know if I'm clear..

          1. It is clear that Plantinga is not speculating out of thin air and thinks he has a winning argument (even if not a conclusive proof). Who said otherwise? My argument was that if you interpret his argument in the way I interpreted it, it is truly convincing.

            The gist of the argument: The case of a concept of absolutely necessary existence is a special case in which logic breaks down and leads us to the conclusion that that existence exists in reality (and not just within logic).

            Yes, it seems to me that even a relatively rational person understands it this way.

  2. This reminds me a bit of the logic of the witness argument of the Kuzari:
    Similar to the proof here, the Kuzari also proves a conclusive claim in the possible way:
    In the language of Rabbi Sharki: Where does the assumption that divine revelation is impossible in reality come from? Because no people in history have claimed collective divine revelation.
    Since there is a people who have claimed this revelation. The Jewish people. This means that this revelation is not inevitable.
    Because it is not inevitable. And there is a people who have claimed it. It is necessarily true.
    Although the witness argument goes one more logical step further and thus remains “strong”.
    Not only is it not inevitable but it must be true. Because a national event that is the founder of a nation. cannot be false. We have not found a nation that was founded on a false founding foundation.

    One can argue. But I only brought the principle that is similar to and based on a logically correct argument. After 3 points that prove why this is within the realm of possibility. You need evidence to prove why it is necessary and proven according to actual reality.
    And here the same thinker you quoted was wise to use the fact that after he showed in 3 points that the concept of God is possible in all worlds. Also a fourth point that shows realistic confirmation of why he does exist in practice in the world we know.

  3. Note that I am not claiming that there is a circumstantial (inductive) or logical-causal connection (it necessarily leads to this).

    But there is a similarity in the form of intuitive thinking that exists between the two arguments

    Both start with an ”attack”(in quotation marks) against the negative claim (there can be no revelation / there can be no God). Then they move on to an argument that supposedly crushes the basic premises of the negative claim (or try to uncover a positive intuition for their claim that is hidden within the negative claim).
    In Amsalem (and I read the column. I know that he is not talking about him but about a thinker who developed or reformulated his claim). He attacks the heretical claim that God does not exist / it is unlikely that he exists because if he is brought up in the imagination and everyone admits that it is possible for him to exist in one of the possible worlds - after all, the obvious conclusion is that he exists.

    The Kuzari (more correctly, Rabbi Sherki's version according to the Kuzari) attacks the philosophers for claiming that there is no divine revelation because He is above the spaces of time and human affairs - and tells them that they themselves think so only because the concept of revelation is foreign to them. But that everyone will admit that if there is a people whose tradition is based on revelation - revelation is true according to their system too. (Or is supposed to be true according to their claim).

    The Kuzari himself did not formulate it that way. But Rabbi Sherki did. And this is one of the modern interpretations of his argument. (And I allow myself to be speculative and say that I am convinced that the French rabbis who translated the witness's argument into modern philosophical language used Amsalem's view)

    But as I said. This is a. My speculation (the last point). And b. The first point finds a similarity between the ways of thinking of the argument. And it doesn't mean that there is a logical or necessary connection between them, or even that they belong to the same genre of proofs.

    1. This is not Anselm's argument but Plantinga's. He is not attacking anything (and neither is Anselm), but is trying to prove a claim. And I still don't see the resemblance. Here we are dealing with a logical argument and you must show that it has no flaws (I claimed that there are). The assumption that something reasonable about which there is a tradition must be accepted is a common sense assumption. Something completely different.

  4. Forgive me for bothering you. The subject interests me. Is it fair to describe the gist of your position as one that claims that synthetic and analytic claims should not be mixed (in Kantian terms)? Did Plantinga, in your opinion, make this mix-up?

    1. I don't think so. I think he mixed up two meanings of 'necessity'. Physical and logical. This can be mapped onto analytical (logical) versus synthetic (physical), but that's not the focus of the debate. I think he simply doesn't notice that there are two different meanings here. I suppose if he had seen this distinction he would have agreed with it too.

      1. I assumed that you would agree that there is a common denominator between your description and Kant's description. However, I think that the Kantian distinction between analytic and synthetic sentences precedes your distinction (between the two types of necessity). In my opinion, your distinction is secondary and derived from the first distinction. Therefore, I think that the criticism of the Kantian move also undermines your position and does so precisely from the root (which he stood on and you did not). Therefore, my move will be to show that the assumption that Kant makes in the background of the distinction between analytic and synthetic sentences is a false assumption and hence his entire move is mistaken (and in any case also entails your move that relies on it).

        So what is the implicit Kantian assumption that I am attacking? What is the focus of the discussion in his view in the background of the distinction between analytic and synthetic? In my opinion, it is the assumption that the content or meanings of sentences/arguments cannot come from intuition. Kant denies the existence of such a capacity. Therefore, in his opinion, a "synthetic" claim of a metaphysical nature such as "God exists" expresses a deviation from the boundaries of meaning and should be judged as empty of content that he calls "theoretical" (a logical claim in your language). Therefore, Kant would also agree with you that Plantinga is quick to attribute, unjustly, necessity to his claims, since analytic claims are truly necessary.

        To refute Kant (and you), all that needs to be done is to show that we have an intuitive ability and that Plantinga uses it here as well. The insight that there is absolutely necessary (or at least about its concept/image) is implanted in us intuitively and only then does the inference called the "ontological argument" come, which describes the connection between the concept and its real existence (the content of the concept). This description itself is not analytical or “logical” and therefore does not claim to have the necessary validity that you have treated it. It is possible, of course, that Plantinga himself does claim that his move is “necessary” but then I would argue in the name of the principle of grace that it is “spoiling” itself. In conclusion, note that I do not claim that my move proves that the ontological argument proves the existence of God. All I wanted to show is that your criticism fails because it misses the point.

Leave a Reply

Back to top button