New on the site: Michi-bot. An intelligent assistant based on the writings of Rabbi Michael Avraham.

Halakha and Morality: “A Kohen’s Wife” – Film and Halakha (Column 542)

With God’s help

Disclaimer: This post was translated from Hebrew using AI (ChatGPT 5 Thinking), so there may be inaccuracies or nuances lost. If something seems unclear, please refer to the Hebrew original or contact us for clarification.

As I wrote at the beginning of the previous column, some time ago I watched the film “A Kohen’s Wife” on the Ma’aleh Film School website. The film was produced by Nava Hefetz Nossen, who proposed, prepared, and shot it together with the students of the school. It is only 24 minutes long, and in my view it is recommended (you can watch it for 10 NIS). The film depicts a situation in which the wife of a kohen is raped, and a discussion ensues as to whether she can be permitted to her kohen husband. The case of a kohen’s wife who was raped is a good example of the tension between halakha and morality, and therefore I devoted the previous column to sketching a general picture of these relations as I understand them. In this column I wish to address the film and the situation through the prism of the previous column and to point out several implications.

The Plot of the Film

We are dealing with a Haredi couple from the Old Yishuv quarter of Jerusalem. The husband learns in a kollel and the wife is apparently a homemaker. One day a man knocks at the door asking for charity; when the wife opens the door he enters and rapes her. The husband is a kohen, and according to law the wife of a kohen who was raped must leave her husband. The question arises whether they can be permitted to continue living together, and the rabbinical court (beit din) deliberates but does not find a solution. The relationship between the couple deteriorates, and they stop living together immediately after the incident until a halakhic decision is reached. The film does not make clear why they separate, but I assume it is because the law forbids them to live together (unless a different decision is reached by the beit din).

The beit din does not find a way to permit them, but the husband receives unofficial advice not to believe her. Since the woman constitutes a single witness (in matters of prohibitions, a single witness—even a woman—is believed), halakhically such testimony is not formal “testimony.” A person must be convinced of the factual state of affairs, and therefore one witness or some other good indication may suffice. The husband of course is not obligated to believe her, and if he does not believe her he is not obligated to divorce her even if there is a single witness. From the film it is clear that, factually, there was rape, and there is no doubt that this is entirely clear to the husband himself. In the end he declares that he does not believe her, and thus they are able to continue living together—although the trauma and their shaken relationship already cast a bit of a shadow over their renewed marriage.

The Film’s Importance

The film does not add much that is new on this topic, but it succeeds in placing the viewer inside the situation. When you watch the film, the understanding that this is a tragedy and a moral injustice leaves the intellect, becomes vivid, and penetrates our gut. I imagine the dayanim who had to make such a decision, to convey it to the couple, and to obligate them to comply—and I would very much not want to be in their shoes. In this sense the film is very significant.

It reminds me of the debates I had around the stories of Yisrael Shachak, who, among other things, recounted such a case in which the dayanim required the couple to separate (see also the previous column on this). My secular interlocutors were appalled by the moral insensitivity of the dayanim and wondered whether they have a heart. Why subject her to an additional trauma on top of the first? Who loses if the couple continues their life together? Why make them and their children miserable when they wish to live together and of course love one another and their children? Indeed a terrible situation, and an intellectual understanding of it is very far from the direct and powerful experience of facing the situation firsthand.

I tried to explain to them that the dayanim presumably have at least as much heart as they do; however, they are bound by halakha, and in this case the halakhic value overrides the moral value. Secular criticism ignores the fact that the religious arsenal of values is broader than the moral arsenal (see the previous column), and therefore it is unwilling to understand and acknowledge that, from the perspective of the dayanim and of anyone faithful to halakha, there is a conflict here—a clash of values. I am certain that the dayanim, who experience the situation and upon whom the terrible duty to rule and instruct this ruling has fallen, undergo moral and human stomachaches far more than any of their critics reclining on white sofas in their living rooms.

On Emotion and Intellect

One may wonder whether watching the film—i.e., emotional involvement in the situation—is an advantage or a disadvantage in rendering halakhic decisions of this sort. I have written many times (see, for example, columns 31, 313, and others) that in the secular world emotion is given a vastly exaggerated weight and reason is disgracefully disparaged (a phenomenon that has penetrated deeply into the religious community as well, at least the modern one), whereas in halakha the situation is the reverse. In my view, the cool rationalism of halakha is one of the least understood points about it among secular people. For them the heart is the sole arbiter in such situations. I once mentioned that I watched a music reality show with some of my children (I no longer remember which), and one of the judges was the singer Shlomi Shabat. When he heard one of the contestants he said to him: “My head tells me no, but my heart won’t let me.” He stopped there, and I immediately asked: So, what did he decide? My children burst out laughing, because it was clear to them (and to me) that there was no question: for him it is self-evident that the heart decides, and therefore merely stating what the heart says suffices for us to know the final decision. That is the norm in our world: if the heart says something, it must surely trump the intellect.

Watching the film again aroused in me that same dilemma (see my article here, and a bit in columns 67, 333, and 467): does participation in the situation and experience help or hinder decision-making in such a case? Is it preferable that the ruling be rendered by a posek or dayan who is distant from the situation and can make balanced, cool decisions, or specifically by a dayan who is involved in it and directly experiences the woman’s terrible suffering? Contrary to the prevalent view, to my judgment it is clear that in principle a distant decisor is preferable, especially in a case like this. A decisor who is close to the situation and encounters it directly may skew judgment due to feelings of compassion for the couple, and that is not proper. The religious value is no less binding and no less important than the moral and human value. The concern for moral error should not be the only concern here. There is also a concern for halakhic error.

Still, there are two advantages to a dayan who does experience the situation himself. The first is that his motivation to turn over every stone and examine every possibility to permit them to continue living together will be much stronger than that of a dayan who is not involved, and that is of course an advantage. He will not miss any halakhic path of leniency that exists for this situation. A further advantage is that sometimes direct encounter brings a better understanding of the situation itself. To understand another’s suffering, empathy is very important; certainly intellectual knowledge that someone is suffering does not suffice. At least for a halakhic leniency that is based on distress and exigency (sha’at ha-deḥak), one needs an understanding from within of the situation and of the suffering entailed. But all this is relevant only if there truly is ground to be lenient due to exigency and only if the distress is indeed a factor in the leniency. Generally, exigency in and of itself is not an argument for leniency. Column 478 is dedicated entirely to this point, where I explained why the fact that morality says to do X is not, in itself, sufficient to rule X, and why the fact that there is exigency is likewise not, by itself, a sufficient basis for a halakhic ruling. I showed there that this is one of the salient differences between the Reform approach and the Modern Orthodox approach.

Naturally, the dayanim meet the couple and experience through them this horrific situation; therefore they are charged with the very difficult task of threading the needle: on the one hand, examining in depth every possibility to permit them to continue to live together—which is relatively easy for one who encounters the situation and the suffering directly. But at the same time they must also take care not to deviate from halakha, and that task is harder. In the end, the leniency must hold water. They must be very careful not to have tomorrow’s newspaper say that they were “courageous,” for there is no greater reproach than that (unfortunately I have not infrequently received such “compliments.” Whenever I get such a “compliment,” the worry arises in me that perhaps I did not act correctly). I do not know since when “courageous” became an epithet attached to those who do what pleases the public and what is more convenient. To me, the truly courageous person is one who acts correctly even if it goes against public sentiment and even if it is less convenient. Acting with reason against emotion is usually the direction of courage; acting by emotion, in most cases, is populism rather than courage.

The Husband’s Lack of Trust

I mentioned that the husband ultimately received advice to declare that he does not believe his wife. That was the only way out to allow them to continue living together. Conscience and morality cry out that this is what must be done, for no one loses thereby and everything is restored. But to my judgment this is not a legitimate halakhic step. There is indeed someone who is harmed by it: truth and the religious value.

As I explained in the previous column, in this conflictual situation the religious value of safeguarding the sanctity of the priesthood stands opposite the moral value of not harming the woman and her family. If factually there was rape, then they are forbidden to live together, with all the pain this entails. The religious value overrides the moral value. True, if the husband does not believe her, then even if in our opinion the factual truth is that there was rape, we do not compel him to divorce her. But when the husband declares that he does not believe her even though in his heart he does, he is simply lying. In such a case they are forbidden to live together, and I do not see how a lip-service declaration changes anything. The law depends on the belief itself, not on statements about belief or disbelief. I can also declare that a piece of pork is beef slaughtered properly and then eat it; would anyone imagine that such a declaration has any value? The fact that here we thereby reach the morally desired result does not change the halakhic consideration. If it does not hold halakhically, it is an illegitimate consideration. The Torah itself, which commands such a couple to separate, presumably took into account the harm to the woman and to the couple and nonetheless instructed us that the religious value prevails here.

To adopt such a ploy—a form of ha’arama (legal stratagem)—essentially means implicitly adopting a secular stance according to which only moral values exist and obligate, and therefore there is no real conflict here. Proponents of this view assume that halakha is only a kind of constraint with which one must somehow cope, even if in a crooked way. This feeling leads to the conclusion that in the end it is proper to circumvent that halakhic constraint “courageously” by every possible means in order to attain the morally desired result—even if that route does not hold water. But again: if that is the “courageous” step, then it is probably not the correct step.

On second thought one might suggest that the husband compels himself to re-examine the situation and to entertain the possibility that perhaps it really never happened. After all, he does not have certainty that this is what happened, even if he tends to think so. So why can’t he rely on the doubt that always exists? It seems to me that this claim too is incorrect. There are always doubts in life, and still we make decisions under uncertainty and on the basis of partial information. The bottom line is our decision, made in light of the data and the circumstances. If the husband, after all, believes his wife—even if not with certainty—he cannot claim that he does not believe her. In the end this is a binary question (belief or disbelief), otherwise we have emptied of content the concept of belief or disbelief, as well as the halakha that distinguishes between a husband who believes his wife and one who does not. If halakha makes such a distinction, then apparently there are situations in which the husband does believe and other situations in which he does not. According to the approach that encourages stratagems, such a law is relevant only to a husband who wishes to divorce her anyway, since such a husband will not resort to a stratagem and declare that he does not believe her. Note that for such a husband the claim that he “believes her” only in order to get rid of her is likewise improper. If the truth is that he does not believe her, then he is forbidden to lie and say that he does. I will return to this point at the end of the column.

An Example: The Paradox of Capital Cases

This reminds me of the paradox regarding a beit din judging capital cases (I believe I mentioned it here in the past). As is known, according to halakha a death sentence cannot be reached unanimously: if all the judges rule for death, the defendant goes free. This law is based on the assumption that such consensus raises suspicion that there was a flaw in the process (because it is unlikely to arise independently). Now imagine a beit din of 23 dayanim judging a murderer. A situation arises in which 22 of the dayanim have concluded that he is liable, and the last dayan has to formulate his position. Internally he is convinced that the defendant is indeed liable, but if he votes for what he truly thinks, the defendant will go free; whereas if he votes against what he really thinks, the outcome in practice will be what he does think should happen. The same holds if the last dayan thinks the defendant is innocent: there too a paradox arises, for his vote will lead to the opposite of what he thinks. What should he do in such cases? It would seem proper to resort to trickery and lie in order to bring the truth to light. Such a “courageous” dayan would surely be praised for acting morally and bringing about the appropriate punishment (to acquit the innocent and convict the guilty).

Well, if this is the “courageous” way, you already understand that it is the wrong way. I have no doubt that it is forbidden to lie and to resort to stratagem in such a case. That dayan must vote exactly as he thinks, and whatever results—results. The reason is simple: halakha established that if the entire panel convicts, the defendant must be acquitted. The situation is that indeed everyone was persuaded, and therefore apparently there was a flaw in the process and the truth is that he should be acquitted. If this dayan lies to bring about what he believes is the correct result, he will in fact bring about a result that is problematic halakhically, even if in his opinion that is what is morally right (to convict or to acquit).

A Look at Ha’arama (Legal Stratagem) in General

It is no secret that halakha contains quite a few stratagems, some already appearing in the Talmud. Many lavish praise on ha’arama as expressing the moral sensitivity of the decisors: when they see that a moral problem arises, they circumvent the law by stratagem. We saw above such a stratagem (that the kohen-husband declares that he does not believe his wife), and I argued that it should not be done. I explained that such a stratagem assumes the secular conception that there are no religious values, only moral ones.

Still, there are quite a few stratagems in halakha. The stratagem of the sale of land in the sabbatical year (heter mekhirah) arouses great controversy in our day, but even the sale of ḥametz and the heter iska—two older stratagems—are not free of problems and criticism. The impression is that halakha relates with equanimity to such “winks,” at least so long as the goal is proper. But as I explained in the previous section, a proper goal does not suffice to ground a halakhic leniency. The goal is at most a motivation to search for such a leniency; the leniency itself must be a mechanism that “holds water” on the halakhic plane.

But if it truly holds water, why call it a “stratagem” at all? It would seem to be a legitimate halakhic opening, and if so one could use it in any situation—even when there is no particular distress or worthy moral purpose. Conversely, in cases where the mechanism does not hold water, it is simply a lie, and then it must not be used even when the goal is worthy. Of course there are particular cases in which halakha itself defines exigency as a reason—such as accepting a single witness to permit an agunah, a sick person with or without danger, or rabbinic prohibitions permitted in cases of great need, loss, or exigency, and the like. But in all of these, the Sages have already incorporated these mechanisms into halakha through rabbinic enactment; therefore it is incorrect to relate to them as violations of halakha in exigency. This is the halakha itself.

The Rema, in the introduction to his work Torat Ḥatat, writes the following (his source is a responsum of Mahari Mintz):

“Behold, I will excuse myself in one matter so that the reader not suspect me: at times I wrote to be lenient in cases of significant financial loss, or for a poor person in an important matter, or for the honor of Shabbat. This is because in those cases it appeared to me that there was a full leniency in accordance with the halakha, only that the later authorities were stringent in the matter. Therefore I wrote that where it is not possible, the matter should be established according to its proper law. And so we find that earlier and later authorities acted thus. And Mahari Mintz wrote in his responsum §15 that a poor person on weekdays and a rich person on the eves of Shabbat are equal; nevertheless the custom is to tell them—this one ‘because of his poverty,’ and that one ‘because of the honor of Shabbat’—so that they not wonder why sometimes one forbids and sometimes one permits.”

One cannot be lenient in exigency or in cases of great loss if the step is halakhically impossible. When we are lenient in exigency, it is only where the matter is permitted in principle, but in ordinary circumstances it is nonetheless proper to be stringent. See at length in my article “On Stringency and Leniency.”

Take as an example the stratagem brought in Berakhot 35b:

“Rabbah bar bar Ḥana said in the name of Rabbi Yoḥanan, in the name of Rabbi Yehuda the son of Rabbi Ilai: Come and see that the later generations are not like the earlier generations. The earlier generations would bring their fruits in through the traksimon (side entrance) so as to obligate them in tithes; the later generations bring their fruits in via the roofs, courtyards, and enclosures (karpefot) so as to exempt them from tithes. As Rabbi Yannai said: produce does not become obligated in tithing until it sees the interior of the house, as it is said: ‘I have removed the sacred from the house.’”

By law, if the fruits do not “see” the interior of the house, they are exempt from tithes; therefore in later generations people resorted to the stratagem of bringing their fruits through the roofs so as not to become obligated in tithes. Note that fruits brought into the house in this way are exempt from tithes by law. The stratagem is merely to use this halakhic route to avoid obligation; there is no prohibited act here and certainly no lie. The fruits are truly permitted, not merely presented as if they were permitted.

Regarding prozbul, Tosafot on “Mi ika,” Gittin 36b, wrote that this is a mechanism that exists in halakha by Torah law (the rule of one who “transfers his debts to beit din”), and the stratagem is only to use it to circumvent the remission of debts in the sabbatical year. The sale of land in the sabbatical year, the sale of ḥametz, and the heter iska are likewise entirely valid mechanisms; the stratagem is merely to use them to circumvent the laws of shevi’it, ḥametz, and ribit.[1]

Survey of an Article

There is an article by a jurist named Yaakov Shapira about the above film and about the prohibition regarding a kohen’s wife who was raped. In the article he surveys paths of leniency taken by the decisors. The starting point of everyone dealing with the topic is, of course, the need and desire to keep the couple together and to prevent the tragedy into which halakha places them. The author assumes that everything the decisors did in this area was driven by that aim. The aim is understandable and worthy, but as I wrote above, it does not suffice to ground a leniency. A leniency must hold water on the halakhic plane. The distress is only a trigger not to give up on examining every halakhic possibility that might help permit them. Therefore, even without entering the motives of the decisors, the leniencies themselves must be examined halakhically if we are to use them. I now wish to briefly go over the arguments for leniency brought there, mainly to sharpen what I have said so far.

The background is in the Mishnah, Nedarim 11:12 (and in the sugyah on Nedarim 90), which records that the Sages did not believe a wife who claimed she had become forbidden (defiled) to her husband, out of concern that she had set her eyes upon another. This is itself a very novel and puzzling claim, for it is unclear how the Sages can cancel a Torah law directly and permit a woman who is Biblically forbidden to her husband to continue living with him. True, as in the case of accepting a single witness to permit an agunah, here too it concerns rules of evidence rather than the substantive law. If the truth is that the woman was not raped, then she is permitted, and the Sages are ostensibly only determining that, factually, she is not believed to say that she was raped. But if that were the nature of the enactment, then this would be Torah law and not rabbinic law. In general, it is difficult to say that, factually, in all these cases we know that the woman was not raped. At most there is doubt, if that. Therefore it is clear to all the commentators that this is a rabbinic enactment, and the difficulties with this are obvious. The situation regarding a single witness to permit an agunah is different: there we are indeed persuaded that, factually, the husband is dead; the only obstacle is the rule that a matter of sexual status requires two witnesses. This is only a rule of evidence; but if the truth is that the husband died, then the woman is in fact permitted even if we lack proof. In the case of a kohen’s wife who was raped, however, it is not a matter of accepting a good piece of evidence that is halakhically invalid; rather the reverse: rejecting good halakhic evidence in order to circumvent the law. That is a very problematic directive.

There is room to discuss what a beit din should do if it is persuaded that, factually, the woman truly was raped. Must it force itself not to believe her and to suspect that she merely wants to leave her husband? That is very implausible. The Rashba there speaks of uprooting a Torah law (apparently proactively—be’kum ve’aseh) “for the sake of the matter” (lemigdar milta), i.e., he views it as an action against the law and claims that the Sages have authority to do so. He apparently understood that this is indeed what the beit din should do, irrespective of its understanding of the facts.

In Responsa Oneg Yom Tov §169 this law is discussed at length, and he says that the Sages uprooted the Torah law; therefore even if the husband does believe her, he is not obligated (and, after Rabbeinu Gershom’s ban, cannot) divorce her. He extends the law stated regarding the beit din also to the husband (that he too should not believe her). As an aside he also raises the possibility (see there more sources on this) of suspecting a husband who says he believes her of doing so because he wants to divorce her. This already goes very far, for here they compel the husband to transgress a prohibition merely because of an unsubstantiated suspicion held by the beit din about the husband himself. One must understand that these suspicions are only remote possibilities, not certainties nor even highly probable. Therefore it is more reasonable to say that the beit din will not force the husband to divorce her if he does not wish to, but it is very implausible that they would prevent him from performing his halakhic duty to divorce her if he himself believes her. That is not the simple sense of the Mishnah.

Indeed, Tosafot there, the Rambam, the Tur, and the Shulḥan Arukh ruled that if the husband believes her, he must send her away—if not because of the law itself, then at least by the principle of “shavyei anafshei ḥatikhah de-isura” (one who declares something forbidden to himself thereby renders it forbidden to himself), i.e., if he declares her forbidden, she becomes forbidden to him even if in our view the factual truth is otherwise. Several authorities (the Maharshal, the Noda BiYehuda, and others) further wrote that even after Rabbeinu Gershom’s ban, which forbids a husband to divorce his wife against her will, there is no possibility to prevent him from divorcing if he believes her. The opposing arguments strike me as so far-fetched that it raises in me the suspicion that they arose only as a stratagem intended to allow the couple to live together. But, as noted, that is very implausible halakhically. If the truth is that there was rape and that is what the husband thinks, he cannot act in self-deception; and even if he does so, he is an offender like any kohen who continues to live with his raped wife.

The article cites a proposal of several later authorities that the husband send a get via an agent and then invalidate it not in the agent’s presence. In such a case the Sages retroactively annul the marriage, and consequently the woman who was raped was a single woman at the time and did not become forbidden to her kohen husband, and he can then marry her again. However, R. Shlomo Zalman Auerbach rejected this possibility for several reasons (perhaps one must also discuss the problem of re’aḥ get—a “whiff of a get”; this is not the place to elaborate). Some proposed that the Sages annul the marriage directly without resorting to the stratagem of invalidating the agent not in his presence, but according to most decisors there is no possibility to annul marriages in our time other than for the grounds established in the Talmud. Note that these proposals are not stratagem but the use of rabbinic authority. This is a different option from the previous one: if indeed such authority exists, then a moral motivation is certainly a basis that justifies its use. But plainly in my view such authority does not exist in our time.

In the article it is implied that all these proposals were intended to allow the woman to continue living with her husband—that is, to advance morality at the expense of law. However, in part it is quite clear that this is not the intent; rather, the point is real law. For example, if the husband truly does not believe the woman, he may live with her because that is the law—not because we are circumventing the law so that they live together. Only when the husband’s lack of belief is itself a stratagem (i.e., factually he does believe her) can that be considered ha’arama; but as I explained, such a stratagem has no halakhic basis. The desire to ease the couple’s plight and prevent their tragedy does not suffice to permit. The beit din is supposed to operate according to rules of evidence; if it has suspicion, it must not act to separate a woman from her husband. But the husband must act according to his own understanding of the facts (whether there was or was not rape).

The Difference Between Beit Din and the Individual

Another important remark that arose also regarding the annulments of marriage in which I participated: if a beit din annuls a marriage by claiming that there was an invalid witness, or that the ring lacked the value of a perutah, or a claim of mistaken transaction (mekach ta’ut)—all of these are not actions of a beit din but halakhic instruction, i.e., the action of a posek rather than of a court. If I know that the woman is not married (because there was an invalid witness, for example), then I must draw her attention to the fact that she is not married. That is all the beit din is doing in such situations, and in fact the woman or husband should have acted thus on their own had they understood the situation. The beit din is merely drawing their attention to the situation and the law; it is not acting as a coercive court rendering a judicial verdict.

Likewise in our case: ultimately the duty to divorce his wife is the husband’s halakhic duty (and of course the very prohibition on living together also applies to the wife), not a judicial decision that requires a beit din. If the kohen-husband knows that his wife was raped, he is obligated to send her away, and there is no question for beit din here. He is supposed to do this himself and to act according to his understanding of the facts. Only if the husband does not do so is intervention by a beit din required to compel him (by the rule of compelling observance of commandments), and compulsion requires a court. Alternatively, if there is a dispute between husband and wife, then a beit din is needed to decide, like any dispute between individuals. Here too, that is the action of a court, not of a halakhic decisor. But the very question whether to divorce or not is an ordinary halakhic question entrusted to a posek, not to a beit din. Therefore the Mishnah that says a beit din should suspect that she “set her eyes on another” is not relevant to the husband. If the matter reaches a beit din and they must formulate a decision, they may be bound by rules of evidence. But the husband does not operate by rules of evidence; if he is persuaded that this is the reality, he must act accordingly. Rabbinic enactments to suspect her and not to believe her plainly do not address the husband.

A Note on Forced Interpretations for Moral Reasons

Following the previous column I received a question from Y.D.:

“And if halakha does not command murdering Amalekite children or raping the captive woman (according to the Re’em)?” I do not oppose your approach; on the contrary, I very much agree with it—but there is no need to multiply disputes.

There are halakhic determinations—such as limitations on wiping out Amalek (his example that children should not be killed)—that are themselves the product of moral considerations. Sometimes the decisors interpret the verses in a certain way so as not to contradict moral principles. Is this a halakhic or a moral consideration? Is it legitimate to employ such a consideration within halakha? It would seem that here morality does enter the halakhic determination itself. Whereas according to my approach in the previous column (where I sharply distinguished between halakha and morality and posited their independence), there would seemingly be no place for this.

I will remind that in the previous column I already noted that even according to my view, if there are several interpretive possibilities, one may certainly choose the one that optimally reduces the dissonance between halakha and morality. In many cases that is what commentators do when they interpret halakha in that way, and as I explained that does not contradict the foregoing dichotomy. By the way, in the case of killing Amalekite children, I wrote to another questioner there that in my opinion this is not necessarily because of the moral consideration, for halakha too opposes punishing one who did not sin (e.g., an oness or a minor), and moreover halakha also forbids murder when it is unjustified (for example, by virtue of the rules of criminal liability). Therefore these interpretations can be relevant on the halakhic plane even if a priori we do not see several equally balanced possibilities for the halakhic interpretation of the case. It is not that morality intervened here but a halakhic consideration.

One may of course wonder whether we ought to act similarly regarding the law of a kohen’s wife who was raped; that is, perhaps we can interpret it in a way that reduces the moral dissonance—or because of the halakhic principle (not only the moral one) that we do not harm the innocent, as we saw in the previous paragraph. But specifically here it is difficult to say so, for in every case of a kohen’s wife who was raped a tragedy results. It is therefore clear that the Torah holds that morality does not override the law here, and I do not see a plausible interpretation that would narrow this law and its tension with morality. By contrast, regarding killing Amalek, one can perhaps say that the Torah’s intent was to kill Amalekites who are adults and not children. Even after the narrowing interpretation, the law of killing Amalek with respect to adults remains. But for a kohen’s wife who was raped, if we narrow it for moral reasons, the law is entirely nullified. Therefore here it is clear that the Torah did not intend that.

One last remark: there may nevertheless be a possibility to change the law, because it is not explicit in the Torah. It is a derashah of the Sages (see Ketubot 51b). If so, it may be that this derashah, which was made in a different period in which other values were prevalent and perhaps there was less sensitivity to the suffering of a woman who was raped, should be changed in our time (see the series of columns on Modern Orthodoxy, especially column 476 in that series, which deals with responding to value change). But that would likely require a Sanhedrin that could change the law and interpret the verses anew.

[1] There are borderline stratagems which I will not enter into here, such as the stratagem regarding the firstborn in Temurah 24b, the stratagem of a firstborn that fell into a pit in Beitzah 26a, the stratagem of “it and its young” that fell into a pit in Beitzah 37a, and more.


Discover more from הרב מיכאל אברהם

Subscribe to get the latest posts sent to your email.

19 תגובות

  1. Hello
    You cited the words of the Rambam regarding the time of need, but in contrast to the view of Shaykh Yosef Rambam at the end [discussion in the introduction of instructions, etc.] that his opinion that time of need is a reason to permit the prohibition of the rabbis, they said and they said [to rely on an individual against many], in fact, you probably alluded to this in your words about mechanisms within the Halacha.
    Admittedly, the Shaykh cites there the words of the Bach that it is possible to rely on an individual against many even in a prohibition from the Torah [and I was really surprised by it], but it seems that the Bach's opinion [if indeed his opinion is as the Shaykh understood it] that such a mechanism from the Torah of relying on an individual in time of need exists. In any case, there is certainly no contradiction in all this to the essence of your words.
    P.S. The Sheik there mentions in his statement in the Kit Sekach case that they did not put their words in place of money. For several years now, I have been puzzled by these Sheik's words, because there they are talking about someone who intentionally sold forbidden foods, and not putting their words in place of money will result in the sinner being rewarded.

    1. As you wrote, this is actually a detail of the halakhic mechanisms that were brought up in the column.
      Regarding the sheikh, he does not write that regarding money, the rabbinical prohibition was rejected, but rather that they did not decree it in order to take money. Just as in order to take money, strong evidence is needed, so he claims that the decree was not decreed in order to take money from a dependent. Like other prohibitions that were decreed from the outset and not retrospectively (for example, invalid divorces that do not require taking it from the second husband or hybrids that do not prohibit the product and iswa'B that do not take their money - which is exactly the same as here, etc.).

    2. You wrote that she was raped in fact. However, for the purpose of the law, a distinction must be made between a fact in reality and a halakhic fact. In reality, Reuven comes out with a knife dripping with blood and Shimon dies, but if there were no witnesses, we would not be required to die because murder is not considered a situation in which we would be required to die. Thus, a woman who was raped without valid witnesses was not arrested even though she was raped in fact.

      1. There is no connection. This is the accepted distinction between legal reality and factual reality. But it only speaks of a bi”d (and even there they exaggerate with it. See my article “What is the decree of the Scripture”). The person himself acts according to reality. I stated this in the column itself. Halacha does not play with ”as if”.

  2. 1. I think that the halakhic source for the fact that a raped woman, or alternatively a “gira” woman is forbidden to be a priest, is the very fact that in the past such a woman was less valuable in the eyes of society, and accordingly a priest who married such a woman would have dishonored the institution of the priesthood, which is why such laws were passed. Therefore, the source of the laws is actually in emotion, the “emotions of the public”. Which actually lays the groundwork behind the claims that one should rule according to reason. In fact, the ruling according to reason of “today” is a ruling based on the &#8221emotions” of the past. These laws are simply not relevant today, society does not see a raped woman as a “defective” woman, and the same applies to a convert.
    2. He went even further and said that all these laws are simply pointless, there is no institution of priesthood, and there is no meaning to being a priest in today's life, even in the religious sphere there are all sorts of remnants of the past, it is simply completely unnecessary, compared to the institution of the rabbinate that supposedly replaced the institution of priesthood, and is supposedly today the most important ”Torah” status to which no restrictions apply, according to the halakhic logic of “contempt” they too were supposed to have some restrictions on marriage.
    3. Also, as long as there is no 100% conclusive proof that a certain person is a priest, i.e. a tree of roots, I do not understand how it is possible to rule that a person is a “cohen” just because of a last name, that is stupid, can the ”cohen” To come and say I am not a priest, what will the court do? After all, how can he prove that he is lying? Alternatively, how can he prove that he is a priest?

    1. 1. Historical-social hypotheses, even if they are correct, are not a tool in the halakhic arena. I hinted at this at the end of the column. But there is no point in all this and emotion or anything.
      2. A nice comment, and it has already been thought about before you. But what to do? There is a prohibition on a priest. The rabbinical institution's interference is no longer relevant.
      3. In order to understand, you have to study. Good luck. I assume there are other areas in which you do not understand, the difference is that there you probably do not write strong opinions. This comment is about all your questions, not just this one.

          1. Can a person whose last name is "Cohen" who wishes to marry a "convert" come before the court and claim that he is not a priest, since he has no proof that he is a "cohen." Therefore, the "convert" is legally permitted to marry him.
            What will the court do?

  3. Dropping a nuclear bomb, I will tell you two stories, (with the second story being a really tragic halacha that touches on the fact, and the husband has not wanted to ask the question to the brother for a year now, fearing the answer, which would make him and his family miserable). The first story I had was when I was volunteering at the Heart of the Brothers, my girlfriend and I got caught, not to our advantage, in a story about Shalom Beit (by the way, Cohen), who were many all the time, and later on he suspected his wife, who was having an affair, and hired an investigator to follow her, and she was caught, and threatened her, and she thanked him, and apologized, and repented and promised not to fall again, and I began to think to myself, why bother doing Shalom Beit, between them, maybe the opposite should be separated, I called Rabbi Shevach Rosenblatt (the story happened over 20 years ago) and then he discussed with me about the matter you mentioned, that there is a connection One that if the husband doesn't believe her, etc. In the end, as it seems to me that he answered me, "Don't do it again." I cut this story short because the main point is the second story, which, as mentioned, concerns the act, since the perpetrator is a close friend of mine (a former Abrecht member who now works for a living told me his chilling story in the past, and now that I read the post, I directed this post to him and he doesn't know what to do.) The story is that one day he is sitting in the bathroom, and goes over his wife's cell phone, for entertainment and leisure, and starts listening to recordings, and nothing less and nothing more. He hears a recording that his wife recorded herself (possibly on purpose, it is possible that the phone was set to record in general, but it seems more likely that it was done on purpose) and here he hears an hour or more of arguments between her and a man, whom he does not know, who I say with caution, apparently, it turns out that there was something between them. Not all of the recording is clear there, but among other things he hears him claiming to her that he is also heartbroken about this whole thing in front of his daughter, and she tells him that if her husband finds out about it, he will kill her, and then he answers her, but You told me he wasn't violent, and is trying to persuade her to divorce him, at what point does he slap her and that you came to Ili today and this without prior notice? And finally he even yells at her, in any case from all this mess, this husband understands that it's really not innocent to say the least, and he is very afraid that there was an affair here, unless he continues to bury his head in the sand, and say there was nothing because there is nothing, he came to his wife with this, and slapped her with this, at first she denied, that she didn't know what he was talking about, after that she stuttered, and then she admitted that something happened to her, which she defines as blackmail, but she can't tell what happened, because it's still traumatic for her, the husband agreed to postpone hearing her version, and when a considerable amount of time had passed, and asked again? Her heart started beating fast, so he left her alone, and it's been a year since then, and every time he asks her, she still doesn't tell what happened, only that he has nothing to fear, he can be calm, she wasn't banned from him, and to this day, she hasn't told what happened or who the guy is, nothing, just pushes to draw a picture, that she was blackmailed, the truth is this friend tells me, it sounds pathetic to me, that she was blackmailed, and doesn't tell him, at the same time every stupidest thing in her life that has happened or hasn't happened to her she shares with him, and suddenly such a traumatic event, she's speechless? But the truth is he shared his dilemma with me, that when he thinks to himself, he says, why should I bother with this? After all, his main fear is that something will turn out to have happened, that she will forbid him, he has no problem forgiving her for the betrayal itself, as long as she doesn't forbid him, because then it's like a sword in his world, he doesn't even want to think about such a possibility, in his darkest dream, (they have several children) What he did do was sit down with the two of us, wander through the treasury of wisdom looking for answers in the Stone of Help, on this very matter of not believing in a woman and the like, but this question keeps nagging at his mind, exactly the point you raised, what is not believing, I wish he would be content and tend to think that nothing really happened, the problem is the opposite, that he would be surprised, if he were present to discover that nothing happened, his heart tells him that it also happened, and after what you wrote happened, he tells me that this is exactly the sad point from which he tried to escape all the time and you came and pulled it out as a trivial matter. In short, these stomach flutters will probably continue to accompany him, as long as he continues to play the ostrich, and doesn't go and really clarify the halacha, and maybe It's good that it's like that, it's better to have a Shuggin, etc. The problem is, what does it feel like to live a married life in doubt, is he committing a mitzvah or a sin of coming to Isner all his days?

    1. Not asking the BID is a policy of ostriches. He does not need to ask the BID but rather act according to the halakha. He can turn to the BID or to the posak if he looks for a way to get a divorce and does not find one. But the obligation to get her out does not depend on asking the BID.
      Regarding the evidence, one must distinguish between suspicion and conviction. Not every suspicion you have obligates you to get your wife out, certainly not after a habera that prohibits forcible divorce. There needs to be evidence of adultery for there to be an obligation to get her out. In particular, one must distinguish between a priest's wife and a Jewish woman, who must only get out if she willingly cheats. It is possible that blackmail is not adultery, and therefore it requires examination.
      In short, ostriches are not a recommended policy. But before making decisions, one must turn to the posak to find a way to get a divorce.

  4. Amir wrote:
    I am putting here a link to a post I wrote at the time about the case of a priest's wife who came to the attention of Rabbi David Manish, the Rabbi of Ternopol and the author of the responsa "Havatzelet Hasharon":

    https://m.facebook.com/story.php/?story_fbid=pfbid02Vxrje4BB6CPWuc6QsJ84VtR3hQveDi8CtjSU48nbferbJnusj8u8PPL8NpKh2zXkl&id=100000175711580

    1. In my opinion, this is a very dubious argument, of course. The judge in the field or the husband is supposed to be impressed and decide. Such sweeping rules are problematic. Beyond that, it is impossible to say that she did not experience trauma and fear that she is not accurate because of the trauma. And the claim that there may have been trauma but not what she describes (but without rape) is extremely narrow, of course.
      It is clear that he is adopting an argument that does not hold water just to please his husband, and this is of course a halakhic lie and is not helpful at all.

  5. In the necessary way (see column 52) we can say in the argument of "What's your point?" that if his trust in her is so low that he really doesn't believe she was raped - maybe we should really tell him to throw her out and that's it
    Or is it already a bit of a rant (as in there). And so on.

  6. Where is the opinion of the Prophet written regarding the killing of Amalekite children and the rape of a beautiful woman?

    1. In the book of Yefet Taar, this title is mentioned in Berayim, paragraph 20.
      Regarding the killing of Amalekite children, this is my suggestion in light of the Maimonides’ method, which states that the killing of Amalek is only for those who have not received the 7 commandments of the sons of Noah. Since children cannot receive the 7 commandments of the sons of Noah, it is impossible to know whether the law of killing Amalek applies to them or not. This can be likened to a Gentile child who was adopted and converted in childhood without his knowledge, who desecrated Shabbat in his adulthood with witnesses and a warning. Can he be killed in court as a Jew who desecrated Shabbat? Of course not. First, he must be informed that he is a Gentile who converted in childhood, and only if he accepts Judaism does he become subject to a Sabbath prohibition, by virtue of which he can be killed as a Sabbath violator. If he rejects the conversion, he will remain a Gentile and the Sabbath prohibition that he violates will not apply to him. Even with the Amalekites, the law of the Amalekites applies only if he did not receive the Seven Commandments of the Sons of Noah, but the refusal to accept can only be done in adulthood (in fact, according to the Maimonides, killing an Amalekite is a religious war, not a racial war).
      This argument can also be applied to a Gentile girl who is raped, who according to the Maimonides is killed according to the law, and the animal must be killed. The Happy Light already writes that if the raped girl received the Seven Commandments of the Sons of Noah, it is commanded to revive her as a resident alien and the act of reviving her rejects the law of killing her. Here too, if the girl raped by Israel receives the Seven Commandments of the Sons of Noah in adulthood, the law of killing her will not apply to her. In order for the law of killing her to apply to her, she must reject the Seven Commandments of the Sons of Noah, and then they will kill her, but this will only happen in adulthood. I am not going into the moral aspect of killing the raped woman here (it should be remembered that for Maimonides, the existence of a son of Noah who did not receive the 7 commandments of the sons of Noah is purely utilitarian and not purposive as for Kant), but only to discuss whether a little girl has the qualities of a daughter of Noah who was killed.

  7. מיכי הוא חמור נושא ספרים עם מוטיבציה גבוהה says:

    Mikhi, are you careful not to write the articles (whether they are pure hate articles or shallow “Torah” study articles that contribute nothing to a single person) while you work in academia?

    I want to mention that you are a person who is funded by public funds, and therefore you should make a very great effort not to invest time in writing your nonsense while the public pays you to do other things that, by the way, also do not contribute too much to the people of Israel (to put it mildly). . .

    By the way, can you mention one thing you did in academia, that you were personally funded with huge sums for a doctorate and two posts, and to this day you teach “Judaism” at Bar Ilan, which was productive in a way that was appropriate enough for the world and the people of Israel?

    Also, we should note that you yourself said that you felt that you were not doing important things. . .
    So why continue to milk the state coffers?
    what for?

  8. I don't think that in the secular public, emotion prevails over reason, unlike the religious public. Even in the ultra-Orthodox public, I see many decisions and resolutions that stem from emotion. In contrast to the secular public, which leads by a wide margin in areas such as exact sciences, mathematics, and entrepreneurship, business, and investments, where there is not much room for emotion. The maximum for understanding the public's emotions and using them.

    In my opinion, the secular who is unable to understand the dilemma is because he does not see halakha as something binding or the word of God, or believes that God only demands morality and has no additional requirements.
    Also the Christian approach, where there is no halakha, only morality. Christians see moral intent in Scripture. This has also influenced the secular Jewish public (and even the religious), which has also mixed it with "modern" moral values. I have seen quite a few ultra-Orthodox, including Talmud Torah scholars, who see moral intent in the Torah and even use it to attack "secular morality."

    I have actually seen quite a few secularists who criticize Halacha for its inconsistency and contradictions and claim that it is a wrong model (just as in mathematics or logic, if you reach two contradictory conclusions, the Torah falls). Here too, they do not understand Halacha and Torah and look at it as they look at other wisdoms.
    And in general, even in matters that are not Halacha, they find two contradictory sayings and claim that this is impossible.
    I have also seen religious people who criticize Christianity as a place of repentance for missionaries, but with similar Halacha concepts they have no problem. They simply do not understand that Christians see these practices and beliefs as binding. A person cannot accept a certain position as a consideration if they are not convinced that it is correct or binding.

Leave a Reply

Back to top button